当前位置:高等教育资讯网  >  中国高校课件下载中心  >  大学文库  >  浏览文档

《Mathematics for Computer》Notes for Recitation 20

资源类别:文库,文档格式:PDF,文档页数:6,文件大小:149.92KB,团购合买
Problem 1. The following two parts are not related. Try them, to make sure you un- derstand the jargon of random variables distributions, probability density functions, etc. Ask your TA if you don't understand/remember what some phrase means. (a)Suppose X1, X2, and X3 are three mutually independent random variables, each having the uniform distribution
点击下载完整版文档(PDF)

6.042/18.] Mathematics for Computer Science April 29, 2005 Srini devadas and Eric Lehman Notes for Recitation 20 Problem 1. The following two parts are not related. Try them, to make sure you un- derstand the jargon of random variables, distributions, probability density functions, etc Ask your ta if you don t understand/ remember what some phrase means (a) Suppose X1, X2, and X3 are three mutually independent random variables, each having the uniform distribution Pr(Xi=k)equal to 1/3 for each of k= 1, 2, 3 Let M be another random variable giving the maximum of these three random vari ables. What is the density function of M? Solution. This can be easily hashed out by counting the possible outcomes M is I with probability 2 with probability 19 3 with probability (b) Suppose X, Y are two independent binomial random variables with parameters (n, p) and(m, p), respectively. What is Pr(X+Y=k)? Solution. The pdf of X is the probability of tossing k Heads out of n independent flips of a coin with bias p. Likewise for Y and m flips. Since, X and Y are inde- endent, the pdf of x+y corresponds to n+ m independent flips, i.e X+y is a Binomial variable with parameters(n+m, p). Hence, n+n k p5(1-p)

� � 6.042/18.062J Mathematics for Computer Science April 29, 2005 Srini Devadas and Eric Lehman Notes for Recitation 20 Problem 1. The following two parts are not related. Try them, to make sure you un￾derstand the jargon of random variables, distributions, probability density functions, etc. Ask your TA if you don’t understand/remember what some phrase means. (a) Suppose X1, X2, and X3 are three mutually independent random variables, each having the uniform distribution Pr (Xi = k) equal to 1/3 for each of k = 1, 2, 3. Let M be another random variable giving the maximum of these three random vari￾ables. What is the density function of M? Solution. This can be easily hashed out by counting the possible outcomes: 1 M is 1 with probability 27 7 2 with probability 27 19 3 with probability 27 (b) Suppose X, Y are two independent binomial random variables with parameters (n, p) and (m, p), respectively. What is Pr (X + Y = k)? Solution. The pdf of X is the probability of tossing k Heads out of n independent flips of a coin with bias p. Likewise for Y and m flips. Since, X and Y are inde￾pendent, the pdf of X + Y corresponds to n + m independent flips, i.e., X + Y is a Binomial variable with parameters (n + m, p). Hence, m + n k p (1 − p) m+n−k . k

Recitation 20 Problem 2. I'm God. Seriously. So, I know everything that everybody thinks In particu lar, I know who each one of the 250,000,000 Americans want to vote for in the upcoming elections. I know that a fraction p=0.52 of them want to vote for the current president. You are mortal. An insignificant dot in space-time. But a quite significant dot among dots. You work close to the president and, within a week, you must answer his agonizing question: " Am I win\ing?"Or, in math jargon(but with the same agony :"Isp>1p"8 Your first idea is to ask me (I'm God). But you haven t talked to me for a long time, so you know I won' t tell you. Your second idea is to call every American, ask them, then divide the yes's by 250 million. But you soon realize there is not enough time(there is a reason or representative democracy). Your third idea. You have no third idea! In your panic as the week is almost over, you start picking Americans at random, call them, and ask Amazingly, thats the correct approach. But you should be careful what you are going to say to the president! Let's see (a) In you first phone call, you pick 1 American uniformly at random, call, and ask whether he/she will vote for the president. What is the probability that the answer is going to be"yes".(i) from my perspective? (ii) from your perspective? How would you model this in terms of coin flips Solution. From my perspective, it's 0.52. From your perspective, it is also 0.52. The only problem is that you dont know that, so you just call it p. Clearly, from your perspective, the first phone call is the same as flipping a coin with an unknown bias, which you call p(and I know is 0.52 (b) In your second phone call, you again pick 1 American uniformly at random, call, and ask whether he/ she will vote for the president. But wait! When selecting the second voter, shouldn 't you exclude the guy that you asked in the first phone call? No What's bad if you exclude him/her? Solution. If you do this, you alter the coin that you are flipping. The bias will decrease or increase, depending on whether the first guy said"yes"or"no",respec tively. The analysis gets messy, so you dont want to do this (c) So, in each one of n phone calls, you pick 1 American uniformly at random and ask. Your plan is to eventually divide the number M of positive answers by n to get P=M. An MIT friend tells you that, as the numerical outcome of a random experiment, this P is a random variable; and that, according to his calculations, Pr(P-p≤0.03)≥0.95 When you are done calling people, you divide to get P, and it's 0. 53. You call the president up and... what do you say? Mr President, p=0.53 Mr President, with probability at least 95%, p is within 0.03 of 0.53!

Recitation 20 2 Problem 2. I’m God. Seriously. So, I know everything that everybody thinks. In particu￾lar, I know who each one of the 250,000,000 Americans want to vote for in the upcoming elections. I know that a fraction p = 0.52 of them want to vote for the current president. You are mortal. An insignificant dot in space­time. But a quite significant dot among dots. You work close to the president and, within a week, you must answer his agonizing question: “Am I winning?” Or, in math jargon (but with the same agony): “Is p > 1 2 ?” Your first idea is to ask me (I’m God). But you haven’t talked to me for a long time, so you know I won’t tell you. Your second idea is to call every American, ask them, then divide the yes’s by 250 million. But you soon realize there is not enough time (there is a reason for representative democracy). Your third idea. . . You have no third idea! In your panic as the week is almost over, you start picking Americans at random, call them, and ask! Amazingly, that’s the correct approach. But you should be careful what you are going to say to the president! Let’s see. (a) In you first phone call, you pick 1 American uniformly at random, call, and ask whether he/she will vote for the president. What is the probability that the answer is going to be “yes”. . . (i) from my perspective? (ii) from your perspective? How would you model this in terms of coin flips? Solution. From my perspective, it’s 0.52. From your perspective, it is also 0.52. The only problem is that you don’t know that, so you just call it p. Clearly, from your perspective, the first phone call is the same as flipping a coin with an unknown bias, which you call p (and I know is 0.52). (b) In your second phone call, you again pick 1 American uniformly at random, call, and ask whether he/she will vote for the president. But wait! When selecting the second voter, shouldn’t you exclude the guy that you asked in the first phone call? No. What’s bad if you exclude him/her? Solution. If you do this, you alter the coin that you are flipping. The bias will decrease or increase, depending on whether the first guy said “yes” or “no”, respec￾tively. The analysis gets messy, so you don’t want to do this. (c) So, in each one of n phone calls, you pick 1 American uniformly at random and ask. Your plan is to eventually divide the number M of positive answers by n to get P = n M . An MIT friend tells you that, as the numerical outcome of a random experiment, this P is a random variable; and that, according to his calculations, Pr (| | P − p ≤ 0.03) 0 ≥ .95. (1) When you are done calling people, you divide to get P, and it’s 0.53. You call the president up and. . . what do you say? • Mr. President, p = 0.53! • Mr. President, with probability at least 95%, p is within 0.03 of 0.53!

Recitation 20 Mr. President, either p is within 0.03 of 0.53 or something very strange (less than 5-in-100) has happened For each statement answer: (i) Are you justified to claim it?(ii) Is it true? Solution. The first statement is clearly off the mark (i) Since you havent asked all Americans, you can only make probabilistic state ments about p (ii) The statement is also false, since p=0.52. However, with a different choice of voters, it could have been true. Of course, even in that case, you wouldnt be justified to claim it The second statement is also wrong (i) The unknown constant p is either within 0.03 of 0.53 or more than 0.03 away of 0.53. In the first case, the probability of it being as you claim is 1; in the second case,it is 0. The crucial point is that you dont know which case holds. You could make the above claim, only if you knew you were in the first case. Sadly, ou dont (ii) The claim is actually true in this case. Since p=0.52, the unknown constant is indeed within 0.03 of 0.53. So the probability that you talk about is 1, and therefore at least 95%. But as we said it could be o and then the statement would be false The third statement is the correct one (i) You are justified to claim this statement. To see why, start with the statement either|0.53-pl≤0.030r0.53-p>0.03 which is clearly true. Now read it as follows: Either p is within 0.03 of 0.53 or it is not and therefore my randomrandom variable P took a value from a set that is hit only 5 times in 100. So, clearly either p is within 0.03 of 0.53 or something (ii)The statement is true. In the particular case, it is true because the first half of it Is true

Recitation 20 3 • Mr. President, either p is within 0.03 of 0.53 or something very strange (less than 5­in­100) has happened. For each statement answer: (i) Are you justified to claim it? (ii) Is it true? Solution. The first statement is clearly off the mark. (i) Since you haven’t asked all Americans, you can only make probabilistic state￾ments about p. (ii) The statement is also false, since p = 0.52. However, with a different choice of voters, it could have been true. Of course, even in that case, you wouldn’t be justified to claim it. The second statement is also wrong. (i) The unknown constant p is either within 0.03 of 0.53 or more than 0.03 away of 0.53. In the first case, the probability of it being as you claim is 1; in the second case, it is 0. The crucial point is that you don’t know which case holds. You could make the above claim, only if you knew you were in the first case. Sadly, you don’t. (ii) The claim is actually true in this case. Since p = 0.52, the unknown constant is indeed within 0.03 of 0.53. So the probability that you talk about is 1, and therefore at least 95%. But, as we said, it could be 0 and then the statement would be false. The third statement is the correct one. (i) You are justified to claim this statement. To see why, start with the statement either | | 0.53 − p ≤ 0.03 or | | 0.53 − p > 0.03. which is clearly true. Now read it as follows: Either p is within 0.03 of 0.53 or it is not and therefore my random random variable P took a value from a set that is hit only 5 times in 100. So, clearly either p is within 0.03 of 0.53 or something strange has happened. (ii) The statement is true. In the particular case, it is true because the first half of it is true

Recitation 20 2nH(a) Pr(# heads≤am)≤ /p p(1-p)(1-an a)7 H(a)=clog- +(1-0)lo901-a Problem 3. A coin that comes up heads with probability p is flipped n times. Find an upper be ouna on Pr(# heads≥Bm) where B>p. Think about the number of tails and plug into the monster formula above Pr(# heads≥Bm)=Pr(# tails≤(1-B)n Now tails comes up with probability 1-p. So the answer is the same as above with a replaced by 1-B and p replaced by 1-p Pr(# heads>Bm)≤,1=8 1-B)n Here were using the fact that H(1-B)=H(B)

Recitation 20 4 Fact from lecture. Suppose a coin that comes up heads with probability p is flipped n times. Then for all α p. Think about the number of tails and plug into the monster formula above. Solution. Pr (# heads ≥ βn) = Pr (# tails ≤ (1 − β)n) Now tails comes up with probability 1 − p. So the answer is the same as above with α replaced by 1 − β and p replaced by 1 − p: 2nH(β) β Pr (# heads > βn) ≤ �2πβ(1 − β)n βn(1 − p) (1−β)n 1−β · · p 1 − 1−p Here we’re using the fact that H(1 − β) = H(β)

Recitation 20 Problem 4. A Gallup poll in November 2004 found that 35% of the adult population of the United States believes that the theory of evolution is"well-supported by the evidence Gallup polled 1016 people and claims a margin of error of 3 percentage points Let's check Gallups claim. Suppose that there are m adult Americans, of whom pm be- lieve evolution is well-supported and(1-p)m do not. Gallup polls n Americans selected uniformly and independently at random. Of these, gn believe that evolution is well- supported and(1-q)n do not. Gallup then estimates that the fraction of america ans who believe evolution is well-supported is q Note that the only randomization in this experiment is in who gallup chooses to poll. So the sample space is all sequences of n adult Americans. The response of the i-th person polled is"yes"with probability p and"no"with probability 1 -p since the person is selected uniformly at random. Furthermore, the n responses are mutually independent (a) Give an upper bound on the probability that the polls estimate will be 0.03 or more too low. Just write the expression; don' t evaluate yet Solution. We can regard each response as a coin flip that is heads with probability p In these terms, qn is the total number of heads flipped. So we have: Pr(qm≤(p-0.03)n) 2nH(P-003) 51-(=0022=0-(0=0p-py (1-(P-0.03)n (b) Give an upper bound on the probability that the polls estimate will be 0.03 or more too high. Again, just write the expression Solution. Reasoning as before and using the answer to the preceding problem gives Pr(qm>(p+0.03)n) ≤-P+003 nH(p+0.03) (1-(P+0.03)n 1-1=(+0)√2r(p+0.03)(1-(p+0.03)n (c) The sum of these two answers is the probability that Gallup's poll will be off by 3 percentage points or more, one way or the other. Unfortunately, these expres- sions both depend on pthe unknown fraction of evolution-believers that Gallup is trying to estimate! However, the sum of these two expressions is maximized when p=0.5. So evaluate the sum with p=0.5 and n= 1016 to upper bound the probability that Gallup's error is 0.03 or more. Pollsters usually try to ensure that there is a 95% chance that the actual percentage p lies within the polls error range, which is q+0.03 in this Is Gallups evolution poll Solution. The probability that the error is 0.03 or more is about 0.07, which mea that p will lie within the error range of a polled fraction with probability 0.93. So our

Recitation 20 5 Problem 4. A Gallup poll in November 2004 found that 35% of the adult population of the United States believes that the theory of evolution is “well­supported by the evidence”. Gallup polled 1016 people and claims a margin of error of 3 percentage points. Let’s check Gallup’s claim. Suppose that there are m adult Americans, of whom pm be￾lieve evolution is well­supported and (1 − p)m do not. Gallup polls n Americans selected uniformly and independently at random. Of these, qn believe that evolution is well￾supported and (1 − q)n do not. Gallup then estimates that the fraction of Americans who believe evolution is well­supported is q. Note that the only randomization in this experiment is in who Gallup chooses to poll. So the sample space is all sequences of n adult Americans. The response of the i­th person polled is “yes” with probability p and “no” with probability 1 − p since the person is selected uniformly at random. Furthermore, the n responses are mutually independent. (a) Give an upper bound on the probability that the poll’s estimate will be 0.03 or more too low. Just write the expression; don’t evaluate yet! Solution. We can regard each response as a coin flip that is heads with probability p. In these terms, qn is the total number of heads flipped. So we have: Pr (qn ≤ (p − 0.03)n) 2nH(p−0.03) 1 − (p − 0.03) (p−0.03)n(1 − p) (1−(p−0.03))n ≤ · p 1 − (p − 0.03)/p · �2π(p − 0.03)(1 − (p − 0.03))n (b) Give an upper bound on the probability that the poll’s estimate will be 0.03 or more too high. Again, just write the expression. Solution. Reasoning as before and using the answer to the preceding problem gives: Pr (qn > (p + 0.03)n) 2nH(p+0.03) 1−(p+0.03) ≤ 1 − p + 0.03 · �2π(p + 0.03)(1 − (p + 0.03))n · p(p+0.03)n(1 − p) (1−(p+0.03))n 1−p (c) The sum of these two answers is the probability that Gallup’s poll will be off by 3 percentage points or more, one way or the other. Unfortunately, these expres￾sions both depend on p— the unknown fraction of evolution­believers that Gallup is trying to estimate! However, the sum of these two expressions is maximized when p = 0.5. So evaluate the sum with p = 0.5 and n = 1016 to upper bound the probability that Gallup’s error is 0.03 or more. Pollsters usually try to ensure that there is a 95% chance that the actual percentage p lies within the poll’s error range, which is q ± 0.03 in this case. Is Gallup’s evolution poll properly designed? Solution. The probability that the error is 0.03 or more is about 0.07, which means that p will lie within the error range of a polled fraction with probability 0.93. So our

Recitation 20 estimates suggest Gallup's poll is not quite large enough to meet the claimed 0.95 probability. Since Gallup is a professional, we expect he's got the poll size right, by by using a more accurate numerical estimation formula -or he may have considered it legitimate to round a very slightly larger margin of error down to 0.03 (d)If we accept all of Gallup's polling data and calculations, can we conclude that there is a high probability that the number of adult Americans who believe evolu tion is well-supported by the facts is 35+3 percent? Solution. No. This is an question of fact, which is either true or false. We can say that either the statement above is true or else a 1-in-20 event occurred during the poll; specifically, Gallup chose an unrepresentative sample. This may convince you that p is"probably"in the range 0. 35+0.03, but there is no way to convert that informal"probably"to a mathematical probability

Recitation 20 6 estimates suggest Gallup’s poll is not quite large enough to meet the claimed 0.95 probability. Since Gallup is a professional, we expect he’s got the poll size right, by by using a more accurate numerical estimation formula – or he may have considered it legitimate to round a very slightly larger margin of error down to 0.03. (d) If we accept all of Gallup’s polling data and calculations, can we conclude that there is a high probability that the number of adult Americans who believe evolu￾tion is well­supported by the facts is 35 ± 3 percent? Solution. No. This is an question of fact, which is either true or false. We can say that either the statement above is true or else a 1­in­20 event occurred during the poll; specifically, Gallup chose an unrepresentative sample. This may convince you that p is “probably” in the range 0.35 ± 0.03, but there is no way to convert that informal “probably” to a mathematical probability

点击下载完整版文档(PDF)VIP每日下载上限内不扣除下载券和下载次数;
按次数下载不扣除下载券;
24小时内重复下载只扣除一次;
顺序:VIP每日次数-->可用次数-->下载券;
已到末页,全文结束
相关文档

关于我们|帮助中心|下载说明|相关软件|意见反馈|联系我们

Copyright © 2008-现在 cucdc.com 高等教育资讯网 版权所有