当前位置:高等教育资讯网  >  中国高校课件下载中心  >  大学文库  >  浏览文档

《比较法》(英文版)THE APPLICABILITY OF COMPARATIVE CONCEPTS

资源类别:文库,文档格式:DOC,文档页数:16,文件大小:130.5KB,团购合买
C.J.P. van Laer(Maastricht University)(1) Readers are reminded that this work is protected by copyright. While they are free to use the ideas expressed in it, they may not copy, distribute or publish the work or part of it, in any form, printed electronic or otherwise, except for reasonable quoting, clearly indicating the source. Readers are permitted to make copies, electronically or printed, for personal and classroom use. Contents
点击下载完整版文档(DOC)

THE APPLICABILITY OF COMPARATIVE CONCEPTS P van Laer(Maastricht University (1) Readers are reminded that this work is protected by copyright While they are free to use the ideas expressed in it, they may not copy, distribute or publish the work or part of it, in any form, printed electronic or otherwise, except for reasonable quoting, clearly indicating the source. Readers are permitted to make copies, electronically or printed, for personal and classroom use Contents 1 Introduction 1. I Comparative concepts 1.2 The applicability of comparative concepts 2. The formation of comparative concepts 2. 1 Extensional concepts 2.2 Functional concepts 2.3 Immanent concepts 3. Comparative concepts of empirical use 3. 1 Extensional concepts 3.2 Functional concepts 3.3 Immanent concepts 4. Comparative concepts on the Internet 4. 1 The Index to Foreign Legal Periodicals 4.2 Comparative thesauruses? 5 Conclusions References Footnotes 1 Introduction 1. I Comparative concepts It is still an open question posed to the discipline of comparative law how to develop a satisfactory set of concepts to be used for stating and thinking about particular problems or hypotheses. To this question, I have elaborated some answers in my doctoral dissertation( Van Laer, 1997; in Dutch) The book has an English summary, which is also available on the Internet (http://www-edocs.unimaas.nl/general/ism1997.htm#cvl).TheEnglishsummarygivesanideaof two subjects, comparative systems of arrangement and characterization in private international law

THE APPLICABILITY OF COMPARATIVE CONCEPTS C.J.P. van Laer (Maastricht University)(1) Readers are reminded that this work is protected by copyright. While they are free to use the ideas expressed in it, they may not copy, distribute or publish the work or part of it, in any form, printed, electronic or otherwise, except for reasonable quoting, clearly indicating the source. Readers are permitted to make copies, electronically or printed, for personal and classroom use. Contents 1. Introduction 1.1 Comparative concepts 1.2 The applicability of comparative concepts 2. The formation of comparative concepts 2.1 Extensional concepts 2.2 Functional concepts 2.3 Immanent concepts 3. Comparative concepts of empirical use 3.1 Extensional concepts 3.2 Functional concepts 3.3 Immanent concepts 4. Comparative concepts on the Internet 4.1 The Index to Foreign Legal Periodicals 4.2 Comparative thesauruses? 5. Conclusions References Footnotes 1. Introduction 1.1 Comparative concepts It is still an open question posed to the discipline of comparative law how to develop a satisfactory set of concepts to be used for stating and thinking about particular problems or hypotheses. To this question, I have elaborated some answers in my doctoral dissertation (Van Laer, 1997; in Dutch). The book has an English summary, which is also available on the Internet (http://www-edocs.unimaas.nl/general/ism1997.htm#CvL). The English summary gives an idea of two subjects, comparative systems of arrangement and characterization in private international law

These subjects are discussed in the book, not in this article. This article is intended to shed light on the arguments given in the other chapters of the book. (2 he core issue of this article is the suitability of comparative concepts for comparat studies. The question of whether such comparative concepts are of any use has not been conclusively. In this article, I have attempted to synthesize some important points from of the literature. But first, some introductory remarks will be made in order to offer a framework Comparative concepts belong to the conceptual apparatus with which the comparatist can approach his discipline, a field which is not limited to only one legal system. Specifically, comparative concepts are concepts that are applied in micro-comparative research, ie. research carried out at the level of parts of legal systems. Correspondingly, comparative concepts are inadequate for dealing with legal families or with legal systems in their entirety. The proposition of this article is that comparative concepts enable us to compare legal rules belonging to different legal systems. Examples of comparative concepts are 'adoption and unjust enrichment, which refer to legal rules within different systems The premise of this article is that comparative concepts are criteria on the basis of which the rules of different legal systems may be compared. The legal rules to be compared must have the intension' of the comparative concept. This condition can be explained as follows: the intension includes the characteristics determining the applicability of the concept. The intension of the omparative concept is important since the intension must be explicit in order to make understandable which characteristics of legal rules account for their comparability 1. 2 The applicability of comparative concepts As stated above, comparative concepts are criteria on the basis of which the rules of different legal systems may be compared. This premise needs some further explanation Clusters of features are associated with terms like 'adoption' and unjust enrichment The comparatist will have to know which legal rules are the referents of these terms. The criteria of comparative concepts must be observable criteria enabling us to investigate empirically the rules belonging to different legal systems. However, the researcher preparing his investigation cannot be sure that the chosen concept includes observable criteria for its application. Results from other comparatists, if available, are not al ways sufficient to justify this conclusion. Therefore, in the first phase of comparative research, it is wise to assume only that legal rules are comparable Comparative concepts do not stand for innate notions which are present in the human mind, but for observable criteria The first phase of comparative research is of primary importance since observable criteria may prevent a waste of time in a later phase. The comparatist wants to study real referents of the comparative concept he has chosen as his starting point. Consequently, a hypothesis must be tested on the legal systems compared. I call a hypothesis containing a comparative concept the comparability assumption An example of such a comparability assumption is the following statement: because of the comparative concept of adoption, the

These subjects are discussed in the book, not in this article. This article is intended to shed light on the arguments given in the other chapters of the book.(2) The core issue of this article is the suitability of comparative concepts for comparative legal studies. The question of whether such comparative concepts are of any use has not been answered conclusively. In this article, I have attempted to synthesize some important points from of the literature. But first, some introductory remarks will be made in order to offer a framework. Comparative concepts belong to the conceptual apparatus with which the comparatist can approach his discipline, a field which is not limited to only one legal system. Specifically, comparative concepts are concepts that are applied in micro-comparative research, i.e. research carried out at the level of parts of legal systems. Correspondingly, comparative concepts are inadequate for dealing with legal families or with legal systems in their entirety. The proposition of this article is that comparative concepts enable us to compare legal rules belonging to different legal systems. Examples of comparative concepts are 'adoption' and 'unjust enrichment', which refer to legal rules within different systems. The premise of this article is that comparative concepts are criteria on the basis of which the rules of different legal systems may be compared. The legal rules to be compared must have the 'intension' of the comparative concept. This condition can be explained as follows: the intension includes the characteristics determining the applicability of the concept. The intension of the comparative concept is important since the intension must be explicit in order to make understandable which characteristics of legal rules account for their comparability. 1.2 The applicability of comparative concepts As stated above, comparative concepts are criteria on the basis of which the rules of different legal systems may be compared. This premise needs some further explanation. Clusters of features are associated with terms like 'adoption' and 'unjust enrichment'. The comparatist will have to know which legal rules are the referents of these terms. The criteria of comparative concepts must be observable criteria enabling us to investigate empirically the rules belonging to different legal systems. However, the researcher preparing his investigation cannot be sure that the chosen concept includes observable criteria for its application. Results from other comparatists, if available, are not always sufficient to justify this conclusion. Therefore, in the first phase of comparative research, it is wise to assume only that legal rules are comparable. Comparative concepts do not stand for innate notions which are present in the human mind, but for observable criteria. The first phase of comparative research is of primary importance since observable criteria may prevent a waste of time in a later phase. The comparatist wants to study real referents of the comparative concept he has chosen as his starting point. Consequently, a hypothesis must be tested on the legal systems compared. I call a hypothesis containing a comparative concept the 'comparability assumption'. An example of such a comparability assumption is the following statement: because of the comparative concept of 'adoption', the

Dutch rules for full adoption can be compared to the Austrian rules governing ' limited adoption Such sentences do not give immediate practical advice; they say something about the legal rules of different systems. If the comparability hypothesis is verified, the Dutch rules are really comparable to the Austrian rules. A comparability assumption which cannot be falsified does not contain observable criteria. To find observable criteria for the comparability assumption, the researcher can begin by analysing legislative definitions in order to determine the respect in which he can compare different legal systems. The following definitions of the Dutch appartementsrecht' and of the GermanWohnungseigentum' will illustrate this seemingly simple preparation of comparative studies. The Dutch 'appartementsrecht'is defined as follows: 'An apartment right means a share in the property which is involved in the division and includes the right to the exclusive use of certain portions of the building which, as indicated by their layout, are intended to be used as separate units.(3)Section I of the German Condominium Act definesWohnungseigentum'differently Residential property is the separate ownership of an apartment in connection with the co-ownership share of the joint property, to which it belongs. (4) Since the right to the exclusive useis mentioned only by the Dutch legislator, this characteristic does not offer a common perspective which could be chosen as a starting point. By contrast, the legislative definitions allow the researcher to compare in the uniform perspective of 'co-ownership. The comparative concept of'co-ownership'is the unequivocal intension which may be part of a comparability assumption. If hypothesis is verified, it is possible to make a real distinction of differences and similarities tween the Dutch 'appartementsrecht' and the German'Wohnungseigentum Concomitantly, I do not consider equivocal intensions to be observable criteria since concepts which prove to have different meanings cause the misinterpretation of research results. These comparative concepts are without empirical use for the reason that they amount to mixing up differences and similarities By definition, comparative concepts that are not applicable in comparative studies, are not applicable either in areas in which comparative law functions as an aid. Correspondingly, I make a distinction between the direct and indirect applicability of comparative concepts: their usefulness in comparative law(direct)and their usefulness in areas of application outside comparative studies (indirect). In sections 2 and 3 the conditions under which comparative concepts are directly useful are discussed; in section 2 three different forms of comparative concepts are dealt with and section 3 examines their relative usefulness in comparative law. Section 4 discusses the Internet as an area of practical application in which comparative law merely serves as an aid 2. The formation of comparative concepts 2. 1 Extensional concepts This section contains a brief analysis of three forms of comparative concepts: extensional concepts, functional concepts and immanent concepts. These forms have to be distinguished before examining their relative usefulness in comparative law, the subject of section 3. First, the formation of extensional concepts will be made clear

Dutch rules for 'full adoption' can be compared to the Austrian rules governing 'limited adoption'. Such sentences do not give immediate practical advice; they say something about the legal rules of different systems. If the comparability hypothesis is verified, the Dutch rules are really comparable to the Austrian rules. A comparability assumption which cannot be falsified does not contain observable criteria. To find observable criteria for the comparability assumption, the researcher can begin by analysing legislative definitions in order to determine the respect in which he can compare different legal systems. The following definitions of the Dutch 'appartementsrecht' and of the German 'Wohnungseigentum' will illustrate this seemingly simple preparation of comparative studies. The Dutch 'appartementsrecht' is defined as follows: 'An apartment right means a share in the property which is involved in the division and includes the right to the exclusive use of certain portions of the building which, as indicated by their layout, are intended to be used as separate units'.(3) Section 1 of the German Condominium Act defines 'Wohnungseigentum' differently: 'Residential property is the separate ownership of an apartment in connection with the co-ownership share of the joint property, to which it belongs'.(4) Since 'the right to the exclusive use' is mentioned only by the Dutch legislator, this characteristic does not offer a common perspective which could be chosen as a starting point. By contrast, the legislative definitions allow the researcher to compare in the uniform perspective of 'co-ownership'. The comparative concept of 'co-ownership' is the unequivocal intension which may be part of a comparability assumption. If this hypothesis is verified, it is possible to make a real distinction of differences and similarities between the Dutch 'appartementsrecht' and the German 'Wohnungseigentum'. Concomitantly, I do not consider equivocal intensions to be observable criteria since concepts which prove to have different meanings cause the misinterpretation of research results. These comparative concepts are without empirical use for the reason that they amount to mixing up differences and similarities. By definition, comparative concepts that are not applicable in comparative studies, are not applicable either in areas in which comparative law functions as an aid. Correspondingly, I make a distinction between the direct and indirect applicability of comparative concepts: their usefulness in comparative law (direct) and their usefulness in areas of application outside comparative studies (indirect). In sections 2 and 3 the conditions under which comparative concepts are directly useful are discussed; in section 2 three different forms of comparative concepts are dealt with and section 3 examines their relative usefulness in comparative law. Section 4 discusses the Internet as an area of practical application in which comparative law merely serves as an aid. 2. The formation of comparative concepts 2.1 Extensional concepts This section contains a brief analysis of three forms of comparative concepts: extensional concepts, functional concepts and immanent concepts. These forms have to be distinguished before examining their relative usefulness in comparative law, the subject of section 3. First, the formation of extensional concepts will be made clear

The formation of extensional concepts is the listing of common elements which may be present in several legal systems. These common elements are to be found at the intersection of different sets of legal rules, or parts of rules, belonging to different systems. In this view, the national sets of rules could be identified by means of legal terms, e.g. the Dutch 'appartementsrecht', the German Wohnungseigentum'and the French 'copropriete des immeubles batis. Without choosing any intension for the comparative concept, the extensional concept of ' apartment ownership refers to the common elements at the intersection The following example will illustrate the formation of extensional concepts. The comparatist may ahl"and of English theft, respectively: W takes moveable property not his own from another with the intention of unlawfully appropriating it to himself shall be punished.. (5)and: 'A person is guilty of theft if he dishonestly appropriates property belonging to another with the intention of permanently depriving the other of it. 'The first rule has been identified by the german legal term Diebstahl and the second one by the term theft in the English Theft Acts. Further, the common elements have to be found at the intersection of these rules. The comparatist may decide that 'property' and'appropriation' are common elements, intuitively excluding unlawfully'and'dishonestly'. He may conclude that the German Diebstahl and the English theft are comparable since extensional concepts result from the listing of common elements 2.2 Functional concepts The formation of functional concepts occurs in relation to social problems to which legal rules are a solution. In this view, the starting point for comparison is not to be found in law itself but in social problems. For instance, different rules of full adoption and of limited adoption will be regarded as a means of solving the problems of neglected children. Functional concepts arise from the perspective of social science. This perspective is external to the legal systems under comparison. Correspondingly, the complete abstraction from national concepts must be achieved Functional concepts are expected to refer to legal rules although functional concepts should be completely independent of legal concepts Functional concepts are related to factual needs or problems of different societies. In this view, the legal rules of different systems would produce social effects on human behaviour which, in its turn, is expected to meet the needs of societies. Correspondingly, the comparatist has to identify common needs or common problems and he has to determine which legal rules are solutions to these common problems. Legal rules considered to be solutions justify the formation of the functional concept. These premises underlying the functional approach lead to the starting point for comparison: the functional concept, e.g. 'apartment ownership, permits the comparison of rules of different legal systems in respect of similar needs or problems such as housing shortage 2.3 Immanent concepts

The formation of extensional concepts is the listing of common elements which may be present in several legal systems. These common elements are to be found at the intersection of different sets of legal rules, or parts of rules, belonging to different systems. In this view, the national sets of rules could be identified by means of legal terms, e.g. the Dutch 'appartementsrecht', the German 'Wohnungseigentum' and the French 'copropriété des immeubles bâtis'. Without choosing any intension for the comparative concept, the extensional concept of 'apartment ownership' refers to the common elements at the intersection. The following example will illustrate the formation of extensional concepts. The comparatist may juxtapose the following rules of German 'Diebstahl' and of English 'theft', respectively: 'Whoever takes moveable property not his own from another with the intention of unlawfully appropriating it to himself shall be punished ...',(5) and: 'A person is guilty of theft if he dishonestly appropriates property belonging to another with the intention of permanently depriving the other of it.' The first rule has been identified by the German legal term 'Diebstahl' and the second one by the term 'theft' in the English Theft Acts. Further, the common elements have to be found at the intersection of these rules. The comparatist may decide that 'property' and 'appropriation' are common elements, intuitively excluding 'unlawfully' and 'dishonestly'. He may conclude that the German 'Diebstahl' and the English 'theft' are comparable since extensional concepts result from the listing of common elements. 2.2 Functional concepts The formation of functional concepts occurs in relation to social problems to which legal rules are a solution. In this view, the starting point for comparison is not to be found in law itself but in social problems. For instance, different rules of 'full adoption' and of 'limited adoption' will be regarded as a means of solving the problems of neglected children. Functional concepts arise from the perspective of social science. This perspective is external to the legal systems under comparison. Correspondingly, the complete abstraction from national concepts must be achieved. Functional concepts are expected to refer to legal rules although functional concepts should be completely independent of legal concepts. Functional concepts are related to factual needs or problems of different societies. In this view, the legal rules of different systems would produce social effects on human behaviour which, in its turn, is expected to meet the needs of societies. Correspondingly, the comparatist has to identify common needs or common problems and he has to determine which legal rules are solutions to these common problems. Legal rules considered to be solutions justify the formation of the functional concept. These premises underlying the functional approach lead to the starting point for comparison: the functional concept, e.g. 'apartment ownership', permits the comparison of rules of different legal systems in respect of similar needs or problems such as housing shortage. 2.3 Immanent concepts

The formation of immanent concepts occurs as a result of simplifying national legal concepts Immanent concepts are only criteria for the common characteristics shared by the national concepts being compared. An example of an immanent concept is 'adoption, a concept which exclusively contains the shared characteristics of full and 'limited adoption. Immanent concepts are criteria for common characteristics by abstracting from national characteristics which do no have counterparts in the other legal system under investigation. Specific sanctions connected to violations of legal rules are examples of such national characteristics It should be pointed out here that immanent concepts are non-functional concepts. The formation of immanent concepts does not require complete abstraction from national concepts. In this view the starting point for comparison should be found in law itself, not in social problems. Immanent concepts are neither functional concepts nor extensional concepts. As regards the second distinction, the formation of immanent concepts is not the listing of common elements to be found at the intersection of different sets of legal rules. Immanent concepts do not result from common elements but from criteria commonly used by national concepts. The sameness of intension of immanent concepts entails the comparability of legal rules belonging to different systems 3. Comparative concepts of empirical use 3. 1 Extensional concepts This section contains an assessment of the usefulness of the three different forms of comparative concepts: extensional concepts, functional concepts and immanent concepts. The relative usefulness of these forms depends on their possibilities for empirical use in comparative law. As remarked in subsection 1. 2, the criteria for comparative concepts must be observable and unequivocal, enabling us to investigate empirically the rules belonging to different legal system The comparatist must test the comparability assumption on the legal systems compared since he wants to study real referents of the comparative concept he has chosen as his starting point. These conditions are important to assess the suitability of comparative concepts for direct use. First, the question of whether extensional concepts are of any use will be answered There is a controversy between the well-known comparatists Constantinesco and Kokkini, which helps to assess the relative usefulness of extensional concepts. The common comparative denominator which Constantinesco proposes is nothing more than an extensional concept. He states that common elements are present within several legal systems to provide a common comparative denominator. In his opinion one can start to compare as many legal rules as one desires since sufficient relationships govern the selected rules of different legal systems. He goes further when he asserts that the legal rules to be compared provide their own comparability,at least in the initial phase of comparative research. (6) According to Constantinesco, comparative concepts are useless in the initial phase of research

The formation of immanent concepts occurs as a result of simplifying national legal concepts. Immanent concepts are only criteria for the common characteristics shared by the national concepts being compared. An example of an immanent concept is 'adoption', a concept which exclusively contains the shared characteristics of 'full' and 'limited' adoption. Immanent concepts are criteria for common characteristics by abstracting from national characteristics which do not have counterparts in the other legal system under investigation. Specific sanctions connected to violations of legal rules are examples of such national characteristics. It should be pointed out here that immanent concepts are non-functional concepts. The formation of immanent concepts does not require complete abstraction from national concepts. In this view, the starting point for comparison should be found in law itself, not in social problems. Immanent concepts are neither functional concepts nor extensional concepts. As regards the second distinction, the formation of immanent concepts is not the listing of common elements to be found at the intersection of different sets of legal rules. Immanent concepts do not result from common elements but from criteria commonly used by national concepts. The sameness of intension of immanent concepts entails the comparability of legal rules belonging to different systems. 3. Comparative concepts of empirical use 3.1 Extensional concepts This section contains an assessment of the usefulness of the three different forms of comparative concepts: extensional concepts, functional concepts and immanent concepts. The relative usefulness of these forms depends on their possibilities for empirical use in comparative law. As remarked in subsection 1.2, the criteria for comparative concepts must be observable and unequivocal, enabling us to investigate empirically the rules belonging to different legal systems. The comparatist must test the comparability assumption on the legal systems compared since he wants to study real referents of the comparative concept he has chosen as his starting point. These conditions are important to assess the suitability of comparative concepts for direct use. First, the question of whether extensional concepts are of any use will be answered. There is a controversy between the well-known comparatists Constantinesco and Kokkini, which helps to assess the relative usefulness of extensional concepts. The common comparative denominator which Constantinesco proposes is nothing more than an extensional concept. He states that common elements are present within several legal systems to provide a common comparative denominator. In his opinion one can start to compare as many legal rules as one desires since sufficient relationships govern the selected rules of different legal systems. He goes further when he asserts that the legal rules to be compared provide their own comparability, at least in the initial phase of comparative research.(6) According to Constantinesco, comparative concepts are useless in the initial phase of research

Contrary to the views expressed by Constantinesco, Kokkini postulates the suitability of comparative concepts for direct use in the initial phase of comparative research. (7) Comparative concepts are important since they prevent a waste of time in a later phase of research. Testing the comparability assumption must take place as soon as possible to exclude disappointments after visiting many libraries in different countries in order to study information which proves to be serve as unequivocal starting points, which must be upheld in later phases of comparison ncepts irrelevant because of the absence of comparability. According to Kokkini, comparative concepts The controversy between Constantinesco and Kokkini does not decisively assess the relative usefulness of extensional concepts since Kokkini does not explicitly reject the empirical use of extensional concepts. Therefore, I have developed the following arguments against extensional concepts: national terms cannot identify the common elements of, e.g., 'apartment ownership. The intersection containing the common elements can only be identified if the common characteristics of these rules are known. Rules are at the intersection of different legal systems if and only if they ave the characteristics included in the common intension of the comparative concept. As will be shown, extensional concepts do not comply with the conditions explained in subsections 1. 1 and 1.2, stating that the intension of the comparative concept must be explicit and unequivocal The juxtaposition of legal rules, e.g. those of the German 'Diebstahl and of the English theft' mentioned in subsection 2. 1 above, is not sufficient to conclude that common elements are present. After all, the national terms Diebstahl"and theft only refer to German and Engli respectively, without relating these rules. A listing of national terms does not determine the intension to establish that property' and appropriation are two similarities justifying the comparability of the German 'Diebstahl" and the English theft. The terms 'unlawfully' and dishonestly could also belong to the common elements. The comparatist cannot objectively exclude these elements as being purely national elements without using the criteria that goods must be moveable and that it must be possible for another person to own them. The comparatist eds a uniform perspective like that of'co-ownership' in the context of 'apartment ownership described in subsection 1.2. Terminological resemblance does not guarantee any conceptual correspondence fixing the comparability of the rules of different legal systems. Extensional concepts do not necessarily provide observable criteria that enable us to investigate empirically the rules belonging to different legal systems Extensional concepts do not justify the comparability of legal rules. They do not make understandable which characteristics of foreign legal rules account for their comparability. The legal rules to be compared do not provide their own comparability. Comparability is not a given fact which is without doubt. Therefore, it has to be discussed which concepts are useful to compare legal rules: functional concepts on the one hand, or immanent concepts on the other 3.2 Functional concepts

Contrary to the views expressed by Constantinesco, Kokkini postulates the suitability of comparative concepts for direct use in the initial phase of comparative research.(7) Comparative concepts are important since they prevent a waste of time in a later phase of research. Testing the comparability assumption must take place as soon as possible to exclude disappointments after visiting many libraries in different countries in order to study information which proves to be irrelevant because of the absence of comparability. According to Kokkini, comparative concepts serve as unequivocal starting points, which must be upheld in later phases of comparison. The controversy between Constantinesco and Kokkini does not decisively assess the relative usefulness of extensional concepts since Kokkini does not explicitly reject the empirical use of extensional concepts. Therefore, I have developed the following arguments against extensional concepts: national terms cannot identify the common elements of, e.g., 'apartment ownership'. The intersection containing the common elements can only be identified if the common characteristics of these rules are known. Rules are at the intersection of different legal systems if and only if they have the characteristics included in the common intension of the comparative concept. As will be shown, extensional concepts do not comply with the conditions explained in subsections 1.1 and 1.2, stating that the intension of the comparative concept must be explicit and unequivocal. The juxtaposition of legal rules, e.g. those of the German 'Diebstahl' and of the English 'theft' mentioned in subsection 2.1 above, is not sufficient to conclude that common elements are present. After all, the national terms 'Diebstahl' and 'theft' only refer to German and English rules, respectively, without relating these rules. A listing of national terms does not determine the intension to establish that 'property' and 'appropriation' are two similarities justifying the comparability of the German 'Diebstahl' and the English 'theft'. The terms 'unlawfully' and 'dishonestly' could also belong to the common elements. The comparatist cannot objectively exclude these elements as being purely national elements without using the criteria that goods must be moveable and that it must be possible for another person to own them. The comparatist needs a uniform perspective like that of 'co-ownership' in the context of 'apartment ownership' described in subsection 1.2. Terminological resemblance does not guarantee any conceptual correspondence fixing the comparability of the rules of different legal systems. Extensional concepts do not necessarily provide observable criteria that enable us to investigate empirically the rules belonging to different legal systems. Extensional concepts do not justify the comparability of legal rules. They do not make understandable which characteristics of foreign legal rules account for their comparability. The legal rules to be compared do not provide their own comparability. Comparability is not a given fact which is without doubt. Therefore, it has to be discussed which concepts are useful to compare legal rules: functional concepts on the one hand, or immanent concepts on the other. 3.2 Functional concepts

The controversy between Zweigert/Kotz and Constantinesco helps to settle the relative usefulness of extensional concepts since Zweigert and Kotz strongly subscribe to the applicability of functional concepts, whereas Constantinesco rejects their functional approach According to Zweigert and Kotz, (8)a social function is the common perspective the researcher needs. They state that rules of different legal systems can be compared if they serve the same function. In their view, the legal rules of every society essentially face the same problems. As Zweigert and Kotz are sceptical of the conceptual constructs of particular nations, complete abstraction from national concepts is to be achieved with the help of functional concepts Conceptual systems would only generate some order in national law. Thus instead of asking What formal requirements are there for sales contracts in foreign law?', they prefer to ask 'How does foreign law protect parties from surprise? Constantinesco rejects the standpoint held by Zweigert and Kotz (9)His criticism can be illustrated by focusing on the phrasing 'How does foreign law protect parties from surprise? In this exemplary phrasing, Zweigert and Kotz omit the legal concepts of formal requirements and of sales contracts' in the initial phase of comparative research. According to Constantinesco, they do not make a distinction between the various legal problems which have been specified by national rules. His criticism can be summarized in the following way: as concepts for describing legal rules, Zweigert and Kotz's functional concepts are too broad and ill-defined. However, Zweigert and Kotz do not answer Constantinesco' s criticism. No discussion between these scholars has been found in the literature The following arguments may complete the criticism by Constantinesco: in order to test the comparability assumption containing the functional concept, the causal relation between legal rules and the resolution of a social problem needs to be established. The social effect of legal rules is difficult to determine, however, so in most cases Zweigert and Kotz's functional concepts have no empirical use. A further explanation will be given to clarify these additional arguments he formation of functional concepts occurs in relation to social problems such as housing shortage, to which, for instance, the rules of apartment ownership are solutions assuming that the legislator cares about the building of apartments. Consequently, the comparatist has to investigate the societal impact of different sets of rules of 'apartment ownership. Specifically, he has to investigate every desirable or undesirable effect of the legal rules of apartment ownership. Such rules may promote the conforming behaviour of investors in one society, but may not have the same positive consequences in a different society because of impediments to the laws effective functioning. Illustrating one of the most important impediments, some ignorance of the law may intervene between the promulgation of the law and the behaviour of potential investors. The rate of conforming behaviour may vary greatly in the societies under investigation; this circumstance turns the formation of functional concepts into an almost arbitrary decision. Besides, the comparatist is not limited to those rules legally defined as rules of apartment ownership' since according to Zweigert and Kotz, the starting point of comparison should not be found in law itself. If different rules may solve the social problem of housing shortage, the comparatist has to expand his research to functional equivalents such as building regulations

The controversy between Zweigert/Kötz and Constantinesco helps to settle the relative usefulness of extensional concepts since Zweigert and Kötz strongly subscribe to the applicability of functional concepts, whereas Constantinesco rejects their functional approach. According to Zweigert and Kötz,(8) a social function is the common perspective the researcher needs. They state that rules of different legal systems can be compared if they serve the same function. In their view, the legal rules of every society essentially face the same problems. As Zweigert and Kötz are sceptical of the conceptual constructs of particular nations, complete abstraction from national concepts is to be achieved with the help of functional concepts. Conceptual systems would only generate some order in national law. Thus instead of asking, 'What formal requirements are there for sales contracts in foreign law?', they prefer to ask 'How does foreign law protect parties from surprise?'. Constantinesco rejects the standpoint held by Zweigert and Kötz.(9) His criticism can be illustrated by focusing on the phrasing 'How does foreign law protect parties from surprise?' In this exemplary phrasing, Zweigert and Kötz omit the legal concepts of 'formal requirements' and of 'sales contracts' in the initial phase of comparative research. According to Constantinesco, they do not make a distinction between the various legal problems which have been specified by national rules. His criticism can be summarized in the following way: as concepts for describing legal rules, Zweigert and Kötz's functional concepts are too broad and ill-defined. However, Zweigert and Kötz do not answer Constantinesco's criticism. No discussion between these scholars has been found in the literature. The following arguments may complete the criticism by Constantinesco: in order to test the comparability assumption containing the functional concept, the causal relation between legal rules and the resolution of a social problem needs to be established. The social effect of legal rules is difficult to determine, however, so in most cases Zweigert and Kötz's functional concepts have no empirical use. A further explanation will be given to clarify these additional arguments. The formation of functional concepts occurs in relation to social problems such as housing shortage, to which, for instance, the rules of 'apartment ownership' are solutions assuming that the legislator cares about the building of apartments. Consequently, the comparatist has to investigate the societal impact of different sets of rules of 'apartment ownership'. Specifically, he has to investigate every desirable or undesirable effect of the legal rules of 'apartment ownership'. Such rules may promote the conforming behaviour of investors in one society, but may not have the same positive consequences in a different society because of impediments to the law's effective functioning. Illustrating one of the most important impediments, some ignorance of the law may intervene between the promulgation of the law and the behaviour of potential investors. The rate of conforming behaviour may vary greatly in the societies under investigation; this circumstance turns the formation of functional concepts into an almost arbitrary decision. Besides, the comparatist is not limited to those rules legally defined as rules of 'apartment ownership' since, according to Zweigert and Kötz, the starting point of comparison should not be found in law itself. If different rules may solve the social problem of housing shortage, the comparatist has to expand his research to functional equivalents such as building regulations

Comparative investigation of the effects of legislative attempts to use law to solve a social problem requires research in various societies. This complex research must show complete conformity to the rules of law in order to establish that different legal systems can be compared since they serve the same function. As intimated earlier, the social consequences of legal rules are difficult to determine Zweigert and Kotz's functional concepts have their drawbacks since their functional approach rests upon several simplifying assumptions concerning the relationship between needs or problems of different societies on the one hand, and rules of different legal the other 3.3 Immanent concepts First, a distinction has to be made between Drobnig and Eltzbacher's opinions since Eltzbacher is more straightforward than Drobnig. However, modern literature has paid no serious attention to Eltzbacher's views. An explanation may be that the functional approach is the dominant trend in modern comparative law. Explaining why Drobnig has to be considered a representative of the functional approach will help to assess the relative usefulness of purely immanent concepts. The end of this subsection refers to Constantinesco's criticism, which may help the reader to draw the conclusion that immanent concepts are to be preferred to zweigert and Kotz's functional concepts Drobnig takes a middle position. (10)On the one hand, he subscribes to a sociological nature of his comparative concept, on the other hand he selects typical solutions' as utilized within a representative legal system, e.g. the solutions offered by the English trust. According to Drobnig typical solutions are comparative concepts which are useful in presenting the outcome of an investigation, for instance, in the International Encyclopedia of Comparative Law. These typical solutions offer precise descriptions of legal rules since they are not cut loose from their conceptual contexts. So far, the 'typical solutions must be considered to be mmanent concepts embedded in their legal systems. However, being based on sociological concepts Drobnig's comparative concepts are equivocal because they amount to mixing up functional concepts and immanent concepts. The real comparability of the described rules is an open question Eltzbacher's immanent concepts are purely non-functional concepts without reference to social problems. Eltzbacher does not require the complete abstraction from national concepts. He prefers to look for common characteristics by abstracting from those national characteristics which do not have counterparts in the other legal system under investigation. (11) Preferring this partial abstraction, Eltzbacher bases the formation of immanent concepts on common features within the legal regulation of different legal systems. However, he treats the formation of immanent concepts without considering the important testing of the comparability assumption as pointed out in subsection 1. 2 above. In spite of that, I will plead in favour of the empirical use of immanent concepts although the formation of these concepts is difficult As remarked in subsection 2.3, immanent concepts are criteria for common characteristics shared

Comparative investigation of the effects of legislative attempts to use law to solve a social problem requires research in various societies. This complex research must show complete conformity to the rules of law in order to establish that different legal systems can be compared since they serve the same function. As intimated earlier, the social consequences of legal rules are difficult to determine. Zweigert and Kötz's functional concepts have their drawbacks since their functional approach rests upon several simplifying assumptions concerning the relationship between needs or problems of different societies on the one hand, and rules of different legal systems on the other. 3.3 Immanent concepts First, a distinction has to be made between Drobnig and Eltzbacher's opinions since Eltzbacher is more straightforward than Drobnig. However, modern literature has paid no serious attention to Eltzbacher's views. An explanation may be that the functional approach is the dominant trend in modern comparative law. Explaining why Drobnig has to be considered a representative of the functional approach will help to assess the relative usefulness of purely immanent concepts. The end of this subsection refers to Constantinesco's criticism, which may help the reader to draw the conclusion that immanent concepts are to be preferred to Zweigert and Kötz's functional concepts. Drobnig takes a middle position.(10) On the one hand, he subscribes to a sociological nature of his comparative concept, on the other hand he selects 'typical solutions' as utilized within a representative legal system, e.g. the solutions offered by the English 'trust'. According to Drobnig, 'typical solutions' are comparative concepts which are useful in presenting the outcome of an investigation, for instance, in the International Encyclopedia of Comparative Law. These 'typical solutions' offer precise descriptions of legal rules since they are not cut loose from their conceptual contexts. So far, the 'typical solutions' must be considered to be immanent concepts embedded in their legal systems. However, being based on sociological concepts Drobnig's comparative concepts are equivocal because they amount to mixing up functional concepts and immanent concepts. The real comparability of the described rules is an open question. Eltzbacher's immanent concepts are purely non-functional concepts without reference to social problems. Eltzbacher does not require the complete abstraction from national concepts. He prefers to look for common characteristics by abstracting from those national characteristics which do not have counterparts in the other legal system under investigation.(11) Preferring this partial abstraction, Eltzbacher bases the formation of immanent concepts on common features within the legal regulation of different legal systems. However, he treats the formation of immanent concepts without considering the important testing of the comparability assumption as pointed out in subsection 1.2 above. In spite of that, I will plead in favour of the empirical use of immanent concepts although the formation of these concepts is difficult. As remarked in subsection 2.3, immanent concepts are criteria for common characteristics shared

by the national concepts being compared. Preparing an empirical investigation concerning adoption, the French researcher, for example, has to recognize the distinction between the national concepts 'adoption pleniere' and 'adoption simple in order to determine the respect in which he wants to compare different legal systems. This distinction must be made since the comparative concept of full adoption does not refer to foreign legal rules corresponding to the French 'adoption simple or limited adoption. Juxtaposing articles 356 and 364 of the French Civil Code may help the comparatist to find the intension for this distinction: 'Adoption confers on the child a filiation which substitutes for its original filiation, the adopted child ceases to belong to its family of blood,. and: 'An adopted child remains in his family of origin and conserves all its rights therein . (12) The first sentence refers to the effects of full adoption, the second one concerns limited adoption Different legal effects establish the distinction between full adoption and limited adoption within the French system. These national concepts have different intensions Choosing the intension of full adoption, the researcher will exclude those forms of adoption which do not terminate all legal ties between the child and his biological family. The two intensions of full and of limited adoption are immanent concepts applicable to foreign rules. Further, the comparability assumption has to be tested since specific effects connected to legal rules could be national characteristics without counterparts in the other legal system under investigation The absence of legislative definitions makes it difficult to choose an immanent concept in order to determine the respect in which the researcher can compare different legal systems. In a case of absence of these definitions, the formation of immanent concepts depends on the structure of the nceptual systems in which these concepts have been embedded. If these systems show almost the same structures, there is an indication that immanent concepts can be found. However immanent concepts are of no empirical use if the hierarchies of legal systems are too divergent conceptually. Comparing the positions of concepts within their respective hierarchies is important to determine the relationship of these concepts but similar positions do not guarantee any conceptual correspondence fixing the comparability of the rules of different legal systems a common characteristic cannot be found if branches of law do not show sufficient correspondence at higher and lower levels. E.g ' real property' in English law and ' biens immeubles in French law are branches of law missing a common characteristic at a higher. more general, level: while real property' looks to procedure, biens immeubles looks to substance (13) This fact impedes the comparatist in his search for a shared characteristic at a lower, more specific, level in the conceptual hierarchies of the respective legal systems. A common characteristic cannot be found for the English concept of 'chattel mortgage on the one hand, and the French concept of hypotheque mobiliere' on the other. The researcher is confronted with a gap when looking for a conceptual equivalent since the English 'chattel mortgage and the French hypotheque mobilier belong to different branches of law. The lack of a common characteristic at a higher, more general level makes the structure of the conceptual systems being compared too divergent. This fact implies that immanent concepts are of no empirical use in this case. Exceptionally, the researcher could prefer functional concepts According to Constantinesco, Zweigert and Kotz's functional concepts are too broad and ill-defined. Contrary to these concepts, immanent concepts are useful in fine-tuning the

by the national concepts being compared. Preparing an empirical investigation concerning 'adoption', the French researcher, for example, has to recognize the distinction between the national concepts 'adoption plénière' and 'adoption simple' in order to determine the respect in which he wants to compare different legal systems. This distinction must be made since the comparative concept of full adoption does not refer to foreign legal rules corresponding to the French 'adoption simple' or limited adoption. Juxtaposing articles 356 and 364 of the French Civil Code may help the comparatist to find the intension for this distinction: 'Adoption confers on the child a filiation which substitutes for its original filiation; the adopted child ceases to belong to its family of blood, ...'; and: 'An adopted child remains in his family of origin and conserves all its rights therein, ...'.(12) The first sentence refers to the effects of full adoption, the second one concerns limited adoption. Different legal effects establish the distinction between full adoption and limited adoption within the French system. These national concepts have different intensions. Choosing the intension of full adoption, the researcher will exclude those forms of adoption which do not terminate all legal ties between the child and his biological family. The two intensions of full and of limited adoption are immanent concepts applicable to foreign rules. Further, the comparability assumption has to be tested since specific effects connected to legal rules could be national characteristics without counterparts in the other legal system under investigation. The absence of legislative definitions makes it difficult to choose an immanent concept in order to determine the respect in which the researcher can compare different legal systems. In a case of absence of these definitions, the formation of immanent concepts depends on the structure of the conceptual systems in which these concepts have been embedded. If these systems show almost the same structures, there is an indication that immanent concepts can be found. However, immanent concepts are of no empirical use if the hierarchies of legal systems are too divergent conceptually. Comparing the positions of concepts within their respective hierarchies is important to determine the relationship of these concepts but similar positions do not guarantee any conceptual correspondence fixing the comparability of the rules of different legal systems. A common characteristic cannot be found if branches of law do not show sufficient correspondence at higher and lower levels. E.g. 'real property' in English law and 'biens immeubles' in French law are branches of law missing a common characteristic at a higher, more general, level: while 'real property' looks to procedure, 'biens immeubles' looks to substance.(13) This fact impedes the comparatist in his search for a shared characteristic at a lower, more specific, level in the conceptual hierarchies of the respective legal systems. A common characteristic cannot be found for the English concept of 'chattel mortgage' on the one hand, and the French concept of 'hypothèque mobilière' on the other. The researcher is confronted with a gap when looking for a conceptual equivalent since the English 'chattel mortgage' and the French 'hypothèque mobilière' belong to different branches of law. The lack of a common characteristic at a higher, more general, level makes the structure of the conceptual systems being compared too divergent. This fact implies that immanent concepts are of no empirical use in this case. Exceptionally, the researcher could prefer functional concepts. According to Constantinesco, Zweigert and Kötz's functional concepts are too broad and ill-defined. Contrary to these concepts, immanent concepts are useful in fine-tuning the

perspective of investigation. It is even possible to form immanent concepts for shared differences etween legal systems. I will show this advantage of immanent concepts in view of two different methods for protecting members against disinheritance: the first method is to secure a sum of money; the od is to limit the testamentary power by provisions which guarantee a certain share in the estate. The second method is that of the 'legal portion of the Civil The comparatist can limit his subject matter to the 'Pflichtteilsberechtigter'in German law and the Noterbe' in Austrian law. 'Pflichtteil 'in German law only creates an obligation to pay a substitute in money for the value of the share which an heir has in the heritage. The same is true for the Noterbe' in Austria. The comparatist can also limit his subject matter to the Pflichtteilsberechtigter' in Swiss law and the reservataire' in French law. The same german word Pflichtteil' means something else in Swiss law. in Swiss law the 'Pflichtteil is part of the heritage itself: it is not the value of a share in the heritage. In Switzerland the 'pflichtteil' is the guaranteed part of the heritage that is not at the disposal of the deceased Furthermore, the Swiss 'Pflichtteil'is equivalent to the French reserve, 1. e that part of the wealth of the deceased that is reserved fo certain heirs. (14)This example confirms two important statements: (1)terminological resemblance does not guarantee any conceptual correspondence fixing the comparability of the rules of different legal systems, a statement which has been elaborated in subsection 3. 1 above; (2 ible to look at similar ations that legal systems their national concepts. The second statement implies that Constantinesco is right in his assertion that Zweigert and Kotz's functional concepts are too broad and ill-defined. The formation of functional concepts pays only general attention to the intention of legal rules, e.g the intention of a part of a heritage to provide for the needs of certain heirs 4. Comparative concepts on the Internet 4. 1 The Index to Foreign Legal Periodicals The Index to Foreign Legal Periodicals is a bibliography which is available on the Internet. (15) The Index gives access to the contents of selected legal periodicals, excluding all types of source publications. The Index covers several countries, excluding the United States, the British Isles, the British Commonwealth, whose jurisdictions have a Common law basis. Nevertheless, the Index covers a large range, about 30 per cent, of Common law articles. The Index uses English keywords since the majority, about 70 per cent, of its subscribers are in Common law jurisdictions. (16) The editors of the Index to Foreign Legal Periodicals pretend to provide the researcher with an internationally acceptable legal terminology in English. However, the keywords of the Index to Foreign Legal Periodicals have been criticized. The English keywords of the Index evoke associations with Common law terminology since they follow, as far as possible, the keywords of the Index to Legal Periodicals covering Anglo-American periodicals only. As a consequence, the presentation of continental European law is more difficult than with, for example, French

perspective of investigation. It is even possible to form immanent concepts for shared differences between legal systems. I will show this advantage of immanent concepts in view of two different methods for protecting needy family members against disinheritance: the first method is to secure a sum of money; the second method is to limit the testamentary power by provisions which guarantee a certain share in the estate. The second method is that of the 'legal portion' of the Civil law. The comparatist can limit his subject matter to the 'Pflichtteilsberechtigter' in German law and the 'Noterbe' in Austrian law. 'Pflichtteil' in German law only creates an obligation to pay a substitute in money for the value of the share which an heir has in the heritage. The same is true for the 'Noterbe' in Austria. The comparatist can also limit his subject matter to the 'Pflichtteilsberechtigter' in Swiss law and the 'réservataire' in French law. The same German word 'Pflichtteil' means something else in Swiss law: in Swiss law the 'Pflichtteil' is part of the heritage itself; it is not the value of a share in the heritage. In Switzerland the 'Pflichtteil' is the guaranteed part of the heritage that is not at the disposal of the deceased. Furthermore, the Swiss 'Pflichtteil' is equivalent to the French 'réserve', i.e. that part of the wealth of the deceased that is reserved for certain heirs.(14) This example confirms two important statements: (1) terminological resemblance does not guarantee any conceptual correspondence fixing the comparability of the rules of different legal systems, a statement which has been elaborated in subsection 3.1 above; (2) immanent concepts make it possible to look at similar specifications that legal systems give to their national concepts. The second statement implies that Constantinesco is right in his assertion that Zweigert and Kötz's functional concepts are too broad and ill-defined. The formation of functional concepts pays only general attention to the intention of legal rules, e.g. the intention of a part of a heritage to provide for the needs of certain heirs. 4. Comparative concepts on the Internet 4.1 The Index to Foreign Legal Periodicals The Index to Foreign Legal Periodicals is a bibliography which is available on the Internet.(15) The Index gives access to the contents of selected legal periodicals, excluding all types of source publications. The Index covers several countries, excluding the United States, the British Isles, the British Commonwealth, whose jurisdictions have a Common law basis. Nevertheless, the Index covers a large range, about 30 per cent, of Common law articles. The Index uses English keywords since the majority, about 70 per cent, of its subscribers are in Common law jurisdictions.(16) The editors of the Index to Foreign Legal Periodicals pretend to provide the researcher with an internationally acceptable legal terminology in English. However, the keywords of the Index to Foreign Legal Periodicals have been criticized. The English keywords of the Index evoke associations with Common law terminology since they follow, as far as possible, the keywords of the Index to Legal Periodicals covering Anglo-American periodicals only. As a consequence, the presentation of continental European law is more difficult than with, for example, French

点击下载完整版文档(DOC)VIP每日下载上限内不扣除下载券和下载次数;
按次数下载不扣除下载券;
24小时内重复下载只扣除一次;
顺序:VIP每日次数-->可用次数-->下载券;
共16页,试读已结束,阅读完整版请下载
相关文档

关于我们|帮助中心|下载说明|相关软件|意见反馈|联系我们

Copyright © 2008-现在 cucdc.com 高等教育资讯网 版权所有