当前位置:高等教育资讯网  >  中国高校课件下载中心  >  大学文库  >  浏览文档

gametheory《经济学理论》 Lecture 5: Games with Payoff Uncertainty(2

资源类别:文库,文档格式:PDF,文档页数:9,文件大小:139.23KB,团购合买
This lecture, as well as the next, exemplify applications of the framework and techniques developed so far to problems of economic interest. Neither lecture attempts to cover the example applications in any generality, of course; you may however find these topics of sufficient interest to warrant further study.
点击下载完整版文档(PDF)

Eco514-Game Theory Lecture 8: Applications(1)-Simultaneous Auctions Marciano siniscalchi October 12. 1999 Introduction This lecture, as well as the next, exemplify applications of the framework and techniques developed so far to problems of economic interest. Neither lecture attempts to cover the example applications in any generality, of course; you may however find these topics of sufficient interest to warrant further study Auction theory is generally indicated as one of the "success stories"of game theory There is no doubt that the game-theoretic analysis of auctions has informed design decisions of great practical relevance. If you are interested in recent applications of auction theory, youshoulddefinitelycheckoutthefollowingUrl:http://www.market-design.comin particular, the Library section contains downloadable working papers in PDF format) This lecture focuses on the simplest possible setting, in which a single good is offered for sale, and bidders are required to submit their offers in a sealed envelope (so we are ruling out ascending or descending auctions: but see below ) Also, I shall focus on the analysis of"popular"auction forms: Myerson's 1981 paper deals with optimal auctions from a mechanism design standpoint. Finally, I will employ equilibrium analysis throughout Framework and auction forms The basic bidding game form may be represented as follows: each bidder i E N submit a bid ai E Ai=R+(so we rule out negative bids ); given any bid profile a =(aiieN, the auctioneer determines the set of high bidders H(a) according to H(a)={i∈N:≠,a1≥a Finally, the object is randomly assigned to one of the high bidders(each of whom equally likely to receive it), referred to as the winning bidder. Thus, the winning bidder is a high bidder, but only one high bidder will be the winning bidder

Eco514—Game Theory Lecture 8: Applications (1)—Simultaneous Auctions Marciano Siniscalchi October 12, 1999 Introduction This lecture, as well as the next, exemplify applications of the framework and techniques developed so far to problems of economic interest. Neither lecture attempts to cover the example applications in any generality, of course; you may however find these topics of sufficient interest to warrant further study. Auction theory is generally indicated as one of the “success stories” of game theory. There is no doubt that the game-theoretic analysis of auctions has informed design decisions of great practical relevance. If you are interested in recent applications of auction theory, you should definitely check out the following URL: http://www.market-design.com (in particular, the Library section contains downloadable working papers in PDF format). This lecture focuses on the simplest possible setting, in which a single good is offered for sale, and bidders are required to submit their offers in a sealed envelope (so we are ruling out ascending or descending auctions: but see below). Also, I shall focus on the analysis of “popular” auction forms: Myerson’s 1981 paper deals with optimal auctions from a mechanism design standpoint. Finally, I will employ equilibrium analysis throughout. Framework and Auction Forms The basic bidding game form may be represented as follows: each bidder i ∈ N submits a bid ai ∈ Ai = R+ (so we rule out negative bids); given any bid profile a = (ai)i∈N , the auctioneer determines the set of high bidders H(a) according to H(a) = {i ∈ N : ∀j 6= i, ai ≥ aj}. Finally, the object is randomly assigned to one of the high bidders (each of whom is equally likely to receive it), referred to as the winning bidder. Thus, the winning bidder is a high bidder, but only one high bidder will be the winning bidder.1 1

The bulk of the literature assumes quasi-linear preferences(although risk-aversion does play a role, and is analyzed in several papers). However, this is clearly not sufficient to determine payoffs. We still need to specify: (i) how much the object is worth to each bidder we shall assume quasi-linear utility); and (ii)the bidders'transfers to the seller. Moreover unless we assume that players'valuations are known, we need to specify (iii) the form of payoff uncertainty we are interested in Specifying (i),(ii) and (ii) leads to a taxonomy of bidding games With respect to (i), we distinguish between private and interdependent values: in the former setting, each player knows her valuation for the object(but may be uncertain about her opponents' valuation); in the latter, one or more players may be uncertain about her valuation, which will typically be related to other players'valuations and or realizations of underlying state variables. In particular, if the object is worth the same to all bidders, but no bidder is certain of the value, we are in a pure common values setting Payment rules(ii)pin down the auction mechanism, the most popular being first-price, second-price and (to a lesser degree) all-pay auctions Finally, with respect to(iii), whatever information bidders receive or hold(be it their valuation or a signal thereof) may be either independent or correlated A few examples will clarify (i) and (ii: the differences may appear to be subtle, but they are substantial Suppose that each bidder i E N observes a signal si E 0, 1, that F denotes the joint cdf of the signals, and that bidder i s valuation is a function vi: [0, 1 -R+. This is a very common specification of payoff uncertainty n this simplified(but very popular) framework, (i) and (ii) entail restrictions on th functions v; and F respectively. If u (si, S-i)=v(si, s'i) for all s; E 0, 1] and s-i E [0, 1]N-1 then we are in a setting with private values: bidder i's valuation is uniquely determined by her own signal si, which she observes. In the simplest case, ui(si, s-i)= si(which, note well, also entails a symmetry assumption) I Sellers may also set a reserve price: all bids below the reserve price are simply rejected. In this case the object may remain unsold if all bids are below the reserve price. Although Myerson shows that, in certain situations, setting a positive reserve price maximizes expected revenues, we shall simply ignore this 2In the most common auction formats, only the winning bidder is required to pay. However, in all-pay auctions, as the name suggests, all bidders pay their bid. Indeed, one can conjure up just about any kind of payment rule: as long as the winning bidder is a high bidder, you can still call the resulting mechanism an

The bulk of the literature assumes quasi-linear preferences (although risk-aversion does play a role, and is analyzed in several papers). However, this is clearly not sufficient to determine payoffs. We still need to specify: (i) how much the object is worth to each bidder (we shall assume quasi-linear utility); and (ii) the bidders’ transfers to the seller.2 Moreover, unless we assume that players’ valuations are known, we need to specify (iii) the form of payoff uncertainty we are interested in. Specifying (i), (ii) and (iii) leads to a taxonomy of bidding games: • With respect to (i), we distinguish between private and interdependent values: in the former setting, each player knows her valuation for the object (but may be uncertain about her opponents’ valuation); in the latter, one or more players may be uncertain about her valuation, which will typically be related to other players’ valuations and/or realizations of underlying state variables. In particular, if the object is worth the same to all bidders, but no bidder is certain of the value, we are in a pure common values setting. • Payment rules (ii) pin down the auction mechanism, the most popular being first-price, second-price and (to a lesser degree) all-pay auctions. • Finally, with respect to (iii), whatever information bidders receive or hold (be it their valuation or a signal thereof) may be either independent or correlated. A few examples will clarify (i) and (iii): the differences may appear to be subtle, but they are substantial. Suppose that each bidder i ∈ N observes a signal si ∈ [0, 1], that F denotes the joint cdf of the signals, and that bidder i’s valuation is a function vi : [0, 1]N → R+. This is a very common specification of payoff uncertainty. In this simplified (but very popular) framework, (i) and (iii) entail restrictions on the functions vi and F respectively. If vi(si , s−i) = vi(si , s0 −i ) for all si ∈ [0, 1] and s−i ∈ [0, 1]N−1 , then we are in a setting with private values: bidder i’s valuation is uniquely determined by her own signal si , which she observes. In the simplest case, vi(si , s−i) = si (which, note well, also entails a symmetry assumption). 1Sellers may also set a reserve price: all bids below the reserve price are simply rejected. In this case, the object may remain unsold if all bids are below the reserve price. Although Myerson shows that, in certain situations, setting a positive reserve price maximizes expected revenues, we shall simply ignore this possibility. 2 In the most common auction formats, only the winning bidder is required to pay. However, in all-pay auctions, as the name suggests, all bidders pay their bid. Indeed, one can conjure up just about any kind of payment rule: as long as the winning bidder is a high bidder, you can still call the resulting mechanism an “auction”. 2

Otherwise, valuations are interdependent; for instance, a pedagogically useful and con- venient specification is vi (s)= ieN S;. This is known as the "wallet game (note again the implicit symmetry assumption The latter is a specification with pure common values. The expression"interdependent values"allows for intermediate cases such as vi (s)=a;:+2itiS, for some ai>1 either case, the signals si, i E N, may be independent(s F(s)=leN Fi(si) for some collection of one-dimensional cdf's Fi, i E N or correlated; for instance, suppose that there exist N+l i.i.d. random variables o, 11,. N, uniform on 0,1, such that Si=ro+ai for every iE N The key intuition is that, since bids will be functions of the signals, when signals are correlated, bidder i can make inferences about her opponents equilibrium bids based on her own signal. This is of course true regardless of whether values are private or interdependent biste inally, payment rules are relatively simple to specify. In a first-price auction, the winning m2(a) ani∈H(a) 0 i H(a) In a second-price auction, she pays the highest non-winning bid: that m2(a) 0xa,i∈H(a) i g H(a Auctions are modelled as (infinite)Bayesian games. In the simplified setting we are looking at, signals contain all payoff-relevant information(although other formulations could considere ed ). It is typical to let g2= s and t(s)=s1×[0,1]-1 reflecting the assumption that players know their signal, and nothing else. Indeed, in this setting, the distinction between the signal si and the corresponding type si x 0, 1]N-Iis blurred, and I will follow conventional usage by adopting whatever term is most convenient The cdf F is then used to define a common prior on Q. As I have already noted, this has several implications for equilibrium analysis; one could entertain different hypotheses, but this is not the point of today's lecture Also note that the resulting game G=(N, Q, (Ai, ui, tien)is infinite both because action spaces are(Ai=R+) and because the state space is. It should be noted that bidding An 3The idea is as follows: players place their wallets on the table, then bid for the money contained in all allets. Each participant knows how much money she is carrying in her own wallet, but ignores the content of the other wallets

Otherwise, valuations are interdependent; for instance, a pedagogically useful and con￾venient specification is vi(s) = P i∈N si . This is known as the “wallet game3” (note again the implicit symmetry assumption). The latter is a specification with pure common values. The expression “interdependent values” allows for intermediate cases such as vi(s) = aisi + P j6=i sj , for some ai > 1. In either case, the signals si , i ∈ N, may be independent (so that F(s) = Q i∈N Fi(si) for some collection of one-dimensional cdf’s Fi , i ∈ N) or correlated; for instance, suppose that there exist N + 1 i.i.d. random variables x0, x1, . . . , xN , uniform on [0, 1 2 ], such that si = x0 + xi for every i ∈ N. The key intuition is that, since bids will be functions of the signals, when signals are correlated, bidder i can make inferences about her opponents’ equilibrium bids based on her own signal. This is of course true regardless of whether values are private or interdependent. Finally, payment rules are relatively simple to specify. In a first-price auction, the winning bidder pays her bid. Thus, the payment rule m : A → RN + is defined by mi(a) =  ai i ∈ H(a) 0 i 6∈ H(a) In a second-price auction, she pays the highest non-winning bid: that is, mi(a) =  maxj6=i aj i ∈ H(a) 0 i 6∈ H(a) Auctions are modelled as (infinite) Bayesian games. In the simplified setting we are looking at, signals contain all payoff-relevant information (although other formulations could be considered). It is typical to let Ω = S and ti(s) = si × [0, 1]N−1 reflecting the assumption that players know their signal, and nothing else. Indeed, in this setting, the distinction between the signal si and the corresponding type si × [0, 1]N−1 is blurred, and I will follow conventional usage by adopting whatever term is most convenient. The cdf F is then used to define a common prior on Ω. As I have already noted, this has several implications for equilibrium analysis; one could entertain different hypotheses, but this is not the point of today’s lecture. Also note that the resulting game G = (N, Ω,(Ai , ui , ti)i∈N ) is infinite both because action spaces are (Ai = R+) and because the state space is. It should be noted that bidding 3The idea is as follows: players place their wallets on the table, then bid for the money contained in all wallets. Each participant knows how much money she is carrying in her own wallet, but ignores the content of the other wallets. 3

games exhibit serious discontinuities, so that the existence of Nash equilibria, and even best replies(see below) is not guaranteed by the standard machinery Quasi-linearity completes the specification of payoffs: fixing a payment rule m, for any profile a∈A, mot()-m(o)i∈H(a) i g H(a) nalysIs We now consider a few even more special illustrative cases. Before we begin, consider the following definition Definition 1 Fix a bidding game g defined as above, and a player iE N. a bid function for bidder i is a function ai: Si-A That is a bid function is a degenerate signal-contingent randomized action Second-Price Auctions with Private values Let us assume for notational simplicity that vi(s)=si. These bidding games are traditionally analyzed using the notion of weak dominance. An action ai weakly dominates an alternative action a; for type s; of bidder i iff, for all opponent bid functions(a,)i#i and for all realization of the opponents' signals t(a,(a3(s;)≠,sS-)≥t(a1,(a(s)≠i,S,-) and moreover there exists a profile of opponents' bid functions and a profile of signal real- izations for which the above inequality is strict p Lith private values, however, this reduces to the requirement that, for all profiles of onents'actions a_i(not bid tions!) ui( vs-∈0,1 and that the inequality be strict for at least one profile of opponents'actions; this is a consequence of the assumption that s-i does not affect vi(s But this leads to the conclusion that, for any signal realization s E 0, 1, bidder iE N and pair of actions ai, ah, ai weakly dominates a for type si of bidder i iff ai weakly dominates a; in the game without payoff uncertainty defined by G(s)=N, (Ai, ui( s))ieN. This is the game you analyzed in Problem Set 1, so you have already proved the following result

games exhibit serious discontinuities, so that the existence of Nash equilibria, and even best replies (see below) is not guaranteed by the standard machinery. Quasi-linearity completes the specification of payoffs: fixing a payment rule m, for any profile a ∈ A, ui(a, s) =  1 |H(a)| [vi(s) − mi(a)] i ∈ H(a) 0 i 6∈ H(a) Analysis We now consider a few even more special illustrative cases. Before we begin, consider the following definition: Definition 1 Fix a bidding game G defined as above, and a player i ∈ N. A bid function for bidder i is a function ai : Si → Ai . That is, a bid function is a degenerate signal-contingent randomized action. Second-Price Auctions with Private Values Let us assume for notational simplicity that vi(s) = si . These bidding games are traditionally analyzed using the notion of weak dominance. An action ai weakly dominates an alternative action a 0 i for type si of bidder i iff, for all opponent bid functions (aj )j6=i and for all realization of the opponents’ signals, ui(ai ,(aj (sj ))j6=i , si , s−i) ≥ ui(a 0 i ,(aj (sj ))j6=i , si , s−i) and moreover there exists a profile of opponents’ bid functions and a profile of signal real￾izations for which the above inequality is strict. With private values, however, this reduces to the requirement that, for all profiles of opponents’ actions a−i (not bid functions!), ui(ai , a−i , si , s−i) ≥ ui(a 0 i , a−i , si , s−i) ∀s−i ∈ [0, 1]N−1 and that the inequality be strict for at least one profile of opponents’ actions; this is a consequence of the assumption that s−i does not affect vi(s). But this leads to the conclusion that, for any signal realization s ∈ [0, 1]N , bidder i ∈ N and pair of actions ai , a0 i , ai weakly dominates a 0 i for type si of bidder i iff ai weakly dominates a 0 i in the game without payoff uncertainty defined by G(s) = {N,(Ai , ui(·, s))i∈N }. This is the game you analyzed in Problem Set 1, so you have already proved the following result: 4

Proposition 0.1 In any second-price auctions with private values, bidding one's valuation is the unique weakly dominant action. Therefore, the profile of "truthful" bid functions defined by ai(si)= si for every i E N, is a Bayesian Nash equilibrium of the associated bidding game Thus, truthful bidding is a Bayesian Nash equilibrium of the second-price auction regardless of the assumptions one makes about the underlying signal structure. This is viewed as a particularly comforting result: truthful bidding is certainly"focal"in this setting Proposition 0. 1 shows that it follows from the assumption that players do not choose weakly dominated actions. You already know that the(complete-information version of the) game has other Bayesian Nash equilibria If participants bid truthfully, then no bidder has a higher valuation for the object than the winner. Thus, under truthful bidding, the second-price auction places the object in the right "hands; that is, it is an efficient mechanism. 4 Incidentally, you may already know that second-price auctions are special cases of Vickrey- Groves-Clark direct mechanisms. With private values, truthful reporting is weakly dominant in such mechanisms, and always leads to efficient outcomes. Thus, for example, the k-good extension of the second-price auction(known as the Vickrey auction) also achieves efficiency First-Price Auctions with Independent Private values The analysis of first-price auctions requires more work, and more restrictive assumptions. In particular, we need to assume a lot of symmetry: in particular, assume that ui (si, s-i)=v(si) for all s=(Si, S_i)E 0, 1(so the same function v: 0, 1-R+ defines valuations for all players) and Fi= F for all i E I(so signals are i.i. d ) Also assume that v(1)=i<oo and v(0)=0. Finally, we assume that v and F are continuously differentiable, and that the density f= F is bounded away from zero Now observe that since the valuation function is bounded, we can renormalize it without loss of generality so that v (1)=1. Having done this, since both v and F are continuous and v is increasing, we can further simplify both the notation and the algebra, again without loss of generality, by considering an equivalent setting in which v(s)=s and F is replaced with a new cdf G such that the density of any valuation E [0, 1]under the original model f(o(a)), equals the density of x under G, i.e. g(a) We look for a symmetric equilibrium in increasing, differentiable bid function strategy we shall follow is to assume that such an equilibrium profile(alien exists, and derive some conditions which the profile must satisfy in order to be an equilibrium in differentiable bid functions. Then, we show that any profile of differentiable bid functions satisfying the above conditions is indeed an equilibrium aNote well: in this literature, an auction mechanism is deemed efficient if there is at least one equilibrium of the associated game which induces an efficient allocation. Other equilibria may well be inefficient

Proposition 0.1 In any second-price auctions with private values, bidding one’s valuation is the unique weakly dominant action. Therefore, the profile of “truthful” bid functions defined by ai(si) = si for every i ∈ N, is a Bayesian Nash equilibrium of the associated bidding game. Thus, truthful bidding is a Bayesian Nash equilibrium of the second-price auction— regardless of the assumptions one makes about the underlying signal structure. This is viewed as a particularly comforting result: truthful bidding is certainly “focal” in this setting; Proposition 0.1 shows that it follows from the assumption that players do not choose weakly dominated actions. You already know that the (complete-information version of the) game has other Bayesian Nash equilibria. If participants bid truthfully, then no bidder has a higher valuation for the object than the winner. Thus, under truthful bidding, the second-price auction places the object in the “right” hands; that is, it is an efficient mechanism.4 Incidentally, you may already know that second-price auctions are special cases of Vickrey￾Groves-Clark direct mechanisms. With private values, truthful reporting is weakly dominant in such mechanisms, and always leads to efficient outcomes. Thus, for example, the k-good extension of the second-price auction (known as the Vickrey auction) also achieves efficiency. First-Price Auctions with Independent Private Values The analysis of first-price auctions requires more work, and more restrictive assumptions. In particular, we need to assume a lot of symmetry: in particular, assume that vi(si , s−i) = v(si) for all s = (si , s−i) ∈ [0, 1]N (so the same function v : [0, 1] → R+ defines valuations for all players) and Fi = F¯ for all i ∈ I (so signals are i.i.d.). Also assume that v(1) = ¯v < ∞ and v(0) = 0. Finally, we assume that v and F¯ are continuously differentiable, and that the density ¯f = F¯0 is bounded away from zero. Now observe that, since the valuation function is bounded, we can renormalize it without loss of generality so that v(1) = 1. Having done this, since both v and F¯ are continuous and v is increasing, we can further simplify both the notation and the algebra, again without loss of generality, by considering an equivalent setting in which v(s) = s and F¯ is replaced with a new cdf G such that the density of any valuation x ∈ [0, 1] under the original model, ¯f(v −1 (x)), equals the density of x under G, i.e. g(x). We look for a symmetric equilibrium in increasing, differentiable bid functions. The strategy we shall follow is to assume that such an equilibrium profile (ai)i∈N = (a, . . . , a) exists, and derive some conditions which the profile must satisfy in order to be an equilibrium in differentiable bid functions. Then, we show that any profile of differentiable bid functions satisfying the above conditions is indeed an equilibrium. 4Note well: in this literature, an auction mechanism is deemed efficient if there is at least one equilibrium of the associated game which induces an efficient allocation. Other equilibria may well be inefficient. 5

Note that this approach does not establish existence directly: first, no profile of bid functions satisfying the derived conditions may exist(so the second part of the argument may be empty ) second, even if they do exist, they may fail to be increasing and / or differentiable so the first part of the argument may be unwarranted ). To establish existence, one must invoke results from the theory of differential equations With this in mind, note that Bidder i's payoff function when her opponents follow the equilibrium bid functions can be written as follows Iai, si= M/+1P{s-:H(a,(a(s)≠)=JU{}s-a小 That is: if she wins the object by bidding ai, Bidder i's utility is si-ai; for any realization of the signals, she may be the only high bidder, or there may be another high bidder,or there may be two, etc, in which case she wins with correspondingly smaller probability The assumptions we have made simplify the analysis considerably. First, since the model perfectly symmetric, we can drop all indices from actions and signals Second, since we are assuming that the common equilibrium bid function is increasing and that G has a density, ties occur with probability zero( i.e. there is G-almost always only one winner). Thus, only one term(corresponding to =N\i) is nonzero in the above summation. Third, since the equilibrium bid function is increasing and signals are independent, it can be inverted, and the probability that the bid a is the winning bid is given by G(a-(a))N-l; this is the probability that all opponents observe signals which induce them (in the equilibrium under consideration) to bid at most a. Thus, we get U(a,s)=[G(a-1(a)-s-a Now, if a is a best reply to the equilibrium belief, then it must satisfy the first-order condition (N-1)G(a()2ga( s-a-Ga (a)) 0. If the profile under consideration is an equilibrium then the above restriction must hold for a= a(s); this allows one to simplify the expression somewhat. Moreover, since G strictly positive by assumption, we can divide throughout by G(s)-2 to get (N-1)9(ss-a(s)=G(s)a(s); the interpretation in terms of cost-benefit tradeoff should be clear. Another necessary con- dition for a to be a best-reply is a(0)=0. Thus, we have a first-order linear differential equation and a boundary condition; given our regularity conditions, a solution exists and is determined by the above necessary conditions

Note that this approach does not establish existence directly: first, no profile of bid functions satisfying the derived conditions may exist (so the second part of the argument may be empty); second, even if they do exist, they may fail to be increasing and/or differentiable (so the first part of the argument may be unwarranted). To establish existence, one must invoke results from the theory of differential equations. With this in mind, note that Bidder i’s payoff function when her opponents follow the equilibrium bid functions can be written as follows: Ui(ai , si) = X J⊂N\{i} 1 |J| + 1 Pr {s−i : H(ai ,(a(sj ))j6=i) = J ∪ {i}} [si − ai ]. That is: if she wins the object by bidding ai , Bidder i’s utility is si − ai ; for any realization of the signals, she may be the only high bidder, or there may be another high bidder, or there may be two, etc., in which case she wins with correspondingly smaller probability. The assumptions we have made simplify the analysis considerably. First, since the model is perfectly symmetric, we can drop all indices from actions and signals. Second, since we are assuming that the common equilibrium bid function is increasing, and that G has a density, ties occur with probability zero (i.e. there is G-almost always only one winner). Thus, only one term (corresponding to J = N \ {i}) is nonzero in the above summation. Third, since the equilibrium bid function is increasing and signals are independent, it can be inverted, and the probability that the bid a is the winning bid is given by G(a −1 (a))N−1 ; this is the probability that all opponents observe signals which induce them (in the equilibrium under consideration) to bid at most a. Thus, we get U(a, s) = [G(a −1 (a))]N−1 [s − a] Now, if a is a best reply to the equilibrium belief, then it must satisfy the first-order condition (N − 1)G(a −1 (a))N−2 g(a −1 (a)) 1 a 0 (a −1 (a))[s − a] − [G(a −1 (a))]N−1 = 0. If the profile under consideration is an equilibrium then the above restriction must hold for a = a(s); this allows one to simplify the expression somewhat. Moreover, since G is strictly positive by assumption, we can divide throughout by G(s) N−2 to get (N − 1)g(s)[s − a(s)] = G(s)a 0 (s); (1) the interpretation in terms of cost-benefit tradeoff should be clear. Another necessary con￾dition for a to be a best-reply is a(0) = 0. Thus, we have a first-order linear differential equation and a boundary condition; given our regularity conditions, a solution exists and is determined by the above necessary conditions. 6

ncidentally, this is where symmetry plays a role. Without it, Equation(1) would be replaced by a system of differential equations, and a more sophisticated machinery (or some clever trick) is required to establish the existence of a solution. We shall compute it explicitly under the additional assumption that G(s=s, i.e. signals are uniformly distributed. Then the above differential equation reduces to (N-1)s-a(s))= sa(s) whence we can verify immediately that a(s)=Nw s is the only solution satisfying a(0)=0 Given this parametrization, it is easy to verify that the profile(x-s,., N s)is indeed Bayesian Nash equilibrium of the first-price auction. Indeed, it is the only symmetric equi- librium in differentiable and increasing strategies. Note that this verification is necessary, because the differential equation derived above was only a necessary condition for the func- tion a( to be a best reply More generally, it can be shown that Equation(1), along with the boundary condition a(0)=0, indeed defines a Bayesian Nash equilibrium of the game In case you are wondering whether invoking, say, concavity of the objective function to conclude that Equation(1)is also a sufficient condition for a to define an equilibrium, think about the following: the concavity of the objective function U(a, s)depends on exogenously given entities such as v and G, but also on the function a itself Two observations are in order. First, note that bidders shade their bids-the latter is always below their valuation, although the difference shrinks to zero in the limit. However, under the same assumptions about signal distributions and valuations, first- and second-price auctions yield the same expected revenues to the seller To see this in our simple example, note that at any state s, the price paid to the seller equals the second-highest signal; hence, expected revenues are equal to the ex pectation of the second order statistic drawn from an i.i. d. uniform sample of size N. This is (N-2)n(s) ()x-21-G(s)y()ds=N(N-1) ds N+1 On the other hand, expected revenues in a first-price auction equaly times the expectation of the first order statistic sNG(s)-lg(sds=N/sds=N N+1 Again, this is actually an instance of a more general fact(see Myerson's paper for details) assuming we are willing to compare equilibria in different games, first- and second-price auctions are revenue-equivalent with private values

Incidentally, this is where symmetry plays a role. Without it, Equation (1) would be replaced by a system of differential equations, and a more sophisticated machinery (or some clever trick) is required to establish the existence of a solution. We shall compute it explicitly under the additional assumption that G(s) = s, i.e. signals are uniformly distributed. Then the above differential equation reduces to (N − 1)[s − a(s)] = sa 0 (s) whence we can verify immediately that a(s) = N−1 N s is the only solution satisfying a(0) = 0. Given this parametrization, it is easy to verify that the profile ( N−1 N s, . . . , N−1 N s) is indeed Bayesian Nash equilibrium of the first-price auction. Indeed, it is the only symmetric equi￾librium in differentiable and increasing strategies. Note that this verification is necessary, because the differential equation derived above was only a necessary condition for the func￾tion a(·) to be a best reply. More generally, it can be shown that Equation (1), along with the boundary condition a(0) = 0, indeed defines a Bayesian Nash equilibrium of the game. In case you are wondering whether invoking, say, concavity of the objective function to conclude that Equation (1) is also a sufficient condition for a to define an equilibrium, think about the following: the concavity of the objective function U(a, s) depends on exogenously given entities such as v and G, but also on the function a itself. Two observations are in order. First, note that bidders shade their bids—the latter is always below their valuation, although the difference shrinks to zero in the limit. However, under the same assumptions about signal distributions and valuations, first- and second-price auctions yield the same expected revenues to the seller. To see this in our simple example, note that at any state s, the price paid to the seller equals the second-highest signal; hence, expected revenues are equal to the expectation of the second order statistic drawn from an i.i.d. uniform sample of size N. This is Z s N (N − 2)!1!G(s) N−2 [1 − G(s)]g(s)ds = N(N − 1) Z s N−1 (1 − s)ds = N − 1 N + 1 . On the other hand, expected revenues in a first-price auction equal N−1 N times the expectation of the first order statistic, Z sNG(s) N−1 g(s)ds = N Z s N ds = N N + 1 . Again, this is actually an instance of a more general fact (see Myerson’s paper for details): assuming we are willing to compare equilibria in different games, first- and second-price auctions are revenue-equivalent with private values. 7

Notes on interdependent values values-regime: the wallet game. In particular, assume there are only two bidders.pendent I will limit my remarks to the simplest possible example of bidding in an interde Let us consider the second-price auction first. A crucial difference between private- and interdependent-values settings is that players no longer have weakly dominant strategies With private values, a player who bids less than her valuation risks losing the object and gains nothing conditional upon winning because her payment is not determined by her bid, but by her opponent With interdependent values, her valuation conditional upon winning the object depends on her opponents bid function, because the latter determines the set of types against which she wins; thus, indirectly, her own bid determines her valuation conditional upon winning and the entire logic of the Vickrey-Groves-Clark mechanism breaks down Indeed, "truthful bidding"is not even defined, if not perhaps with reference to a fixed quilibrium belief! Thus, we can at best hope to obtain efficiency in equilibrium, not as a consequence of the sole assumption that players do not choose weakly dominated actions Indeed, we shall see that efficiency may fail to obtain in equilibrium Let us solve the wa S1+S2. I claim that game. We need only check that 2s is a best reply for type s against the putative equilibrium belief. Her expected payoff when she bids a is given by U(a, s)= (+s2-2s2)ds2=1。1 which has a maximum at a=2s, as one can easily check; the second-order conditions are also easily verified. Also note that, since values are purely common, any allocation mechanism is trivially efficient. However, there are examples of three-bidder games with interdependent values in which efficiency fails Note that revenues equal twice the expected value of the minimum of two i i.d. uniform random variables,or(from our previous analysis)3 Let us now consider a first-price auction in this setting. I claim than now(s1, s2)is an quilibrium profile. To see this, note that as-a+ and again the claim is proved. From our previous analysis, expected revenues equal the expected value of the maximum of two i.i. d. uniform variates, or(again)3.This, ho is not generally the case for interdependent-values settings

Notes on interdependent values I will limit my remarks to the simplest possible example of bidding in an interdependent values-regime: the wallet game. In particular, assume there are only two bidders. Let us consider the second-price auction first. A crucial difference between private- and interdependent-values settings is that players no longer have weakly dominant strategies. With private values, a player who bids less than her valuation risks losing the object, and gains nothing conditional upon winning because her payment is not determined by her bid, but by her opponent’s. With interdependent values, her valuation conditional upon winning the object depends on her opponent’s bid function, because the latter determines the set of types against which she wins; thus, indirectly, her own bid determines her valuation conditional upon winning, and the entire logic of the Vickrey-Groves-Clark mechanism breaks down. Indeed, “truthful bidding” is not even defined, if not perhaps with reference to a fixed equilibrium belief! Thus, we can at best hope to obtain efficiency in equilibrium, not as a consequence of the sole assumption that players do not choose weakly dominated actions. Indeed, we shall see that efficiency may fail to obtain in equilibrium. Let us solve the wallet game under the second-price payment rule: recall that vi(s) = s1 + s2. I claim that the profile (2s1, 2s2) is a Bayesian Nash equilibrium of the associated game. We need only check that 2s is a best reply for type s against the putative equilibrium belief. Her expected payoff when she bids a is given by U(a, s) = Z 1 2 a 0 (s + s2 − 2s2)ds2 = 1 2 as − 1 2 a 2 which has a maximum at a = 2s, as one can easily check; the second-order conditions are also easily verified. Also note that, since values are purely common, any allocation mechanism is trivially efficient. However, there are examples of three-bidder games with interdependent values in which efficiency fails. Note that revenues equal twice the expected value of the minimum of two i.i.d. uniform random variables, or (from our previous analysis) 2 3 . Let us now consider a first-price auction in this setting. I claim than now (s1, s2) is an equilibrium profile. To see this, note that U(a, s) = Z a 0 (s + s2 − a)ds2 = a(s − a) + 1 2 a 2 and again the claim is proved. From our previous analysis, expected revenues equal the expected value of the maximum of two i.i.d. uniform variates, or (again) 2 3 . This, however, is not generally the case for interdependent-values settings. 8

Micro- Notes on Correlation The foregoing discussion leaves open the issue of correlation vs. independence of signals. I will merely point out the differences between these two cases in a limiting case: you should consult Myerson,s 1981 paper, or Cremer and McLean's paper, for more on the topic Let us consider a two-bidder first-price auction with private values and perfectly correlated als: that is, Pr Thus, as soon as a bidder learns her signal, she also learns her opponent's signal; for all practical purposes, at the interim stage the players are actually engaged in a game with complete information It should be clear that the only equilibrium in the game where both signals equal some sE0, 1] is for both players to bid exactly s, i.e. their valuation(if the winning bidder bids more than her opponent, she gains by reducing her bid; if both are bidding a <s, then either one can gain by raising her bid slightly above a). Thus, there is no shading, and the seller is able to extract the whole surplus from the players the stochastic structure of the signals matter hy case, this simple example emphasizes that This turns out to be a general result. In

Micro-Notes on Correlation The foregoing discussion leaves open the issue of correlation vs. independence of signals. I will merely point out the differences between these two cases in a limiting case: you should consult Myerson’s 1981 paper, or Cremer and McLean’s paper, for more on the topic. Let us consider a two-bidder first-price auction with private values and perfectly correlated signals: that is, Pr{s1 = s2} = 1. Thus, as soon as a bidder learns her signal, she also learns her opponent’s signal; for all practical purposes, at the interim stage the players are actually engaged in a game with complete information. It should be clear that the only equilibrium in the game where both signals equal some s ∈ [0, 1] is for both players to bid exactly s, i.e. their valuation (if the winning bidder bids more than her opponent, she gains by reducing her bid; if both are bidding a < s, then either one can gain by raising her bid slightly above a). Thus, there is no shading, and the seller is able to extract the whole surplus from the players. This turns out to be a general result. In any case, this simple example emphasizes that the stochastic structure of the signals matters. 9

点击下载完整版文档(PDF)VIP每日下载上限内不扣除下载券和下载次数;
按次数下载不扣除下载券;
24小时内重复下载只扣除一次;
顺序:VIP每日次数-->可用次数-->下载券;
已到末页,全文结束
相关文档

关于我们|帮助中心|下载说明|相关软件|意见反馈|联系我们

Copyright © 2008-现在 cucdc.com 高等教育资讯网 版权所有