当前位置:高等教育资讯网  >  中国高校课件下载中心  >  大学文库  >  浏览文档

《法学资料集》(英文版) The Economics of Public International Law

资源类别:文库,文档格式:PDF,文档页数:81,文件大小:466.82KB,团购合买
The Economics of Public International Law Alan O. Sykes" Abstract: This paper is a preliminary draft for eventual inclusion in the Handbook of Law and Economics, A. Mitchell Polinsky Steven Shavell editors. It reviews and synthesizes the work of economists and law and economics scholars in the field of public international law. The bulk of that work has been in the area of international trade, but many of the ideas in the trade literature have implications for other subfields.
点击下载完整版文档(PDF)

CHICAGO JoHN M. OLIN LAW &z ECONOMICS WORKING PAPER NO 216 (2D SERIES) The economics of public international law Alan O. Sykes THE LAW SCHOOL THE UNIVERSITY OF CHICAGO July 2004 This paper can be downloaded without charge at TheChicagoWorkingPaperSeriesIndex:http://www.lawuchicago.edu/lawecon/index.html and at the Social Science Research Network Electronic Paper Collection http://ssrn.com/abstract_id=564383

CHICAGO JOHN M. OLIN LAW & ECONOMICS WORKING PAPER NO. 216 (2D SERIES) The Economics of Public International Law Alan O. Sykes THE LAW SCHOOL THE UNIVERSITY OF CHICAGO July 2004 This paper can be downloaded without charge at: The Chicago Working Paper Series Index: http://www.law.uchicago.edu/Lawecon/index.html and at the Social Science Research Network Electronic Paper Collection: http://ssrn.com/abstract_id=564383

The Economics of public International law Alan o. Sykes Abstract: This paper is a preliminary draft for eventual inclusion in the Handbook Law and Economics, A. Mitchell Polinsky Steven Shavell editors. It reviews and synthesizes the work of economists and lanv and economics scholars in the field of public international law. The bulk of that work has been in the area of international trade, but many of the ideas in the trade literature have implications for other subfields. Recent years have seen a significant increase in research on other topics as well. The paper begins with a general framework for thinking about the positive and normative economics ofpublic international law, and then proceeds to a treatment of specific topics including customary law, strategic alliances and the laws of war, international trade, international investment, international antitrust, human rights law, conflicts of law, and the international commons (fisheries) 1. Introduction International law has been recognized as a distinct field of study within the legal ademy for well over a century, but economically-oriented scholars have paid it elatively little attention. Dunoff and Trachtman(1999). By far the bulk of the law and economics research in international law pertains to the law of international trade Systematic work on other topics is limited at best, although research in the field generally is accelerating and the subject can properly be considered a growth area The relative dearth of prior work, especially formal work, and its concentration on international trade issues, poses a number of challenges for a survey of this sort. An excessive emphasis on international trade will mask the richness and diversity of the field, and obscure rather than illuminate the potential research agenda. Moreover, large segments of the economic literature pertaining to international trade law already receive attention in the three volume Handbook of International Economics series, especially in Staiger(1995a), and in a number of other extant and forthcoming volumes focuse WTO issues including Bagwell and Staiger(2002)and Grossman and Helpman(2002) Accordingly, I have limited the treatment of trade issues in this chapter, emphasizing topics that illustrate broader themes for the economic analysis of international law. Much of the chapter will instead be devoted to a general framework for thinking about international law, along with brief discussions of a number of topics outside the realm of Frank Bernice Greenberg Professor of Law, University of Chicago. I have received thoughtful comments on an earlier draft from Kyle Bagwell, Eric Posner, Steven Shavell, and participants in the Handbook of Law and Economics conference at Stanford law schoo

The Economics of Public International Law Alan O. Sykes* Abstract: This paper is a preliminary draft for eventual inclusion in the Handbook of Law and Economics, A. Mitchell Polinsky & Steven Shavell editors. It reviews and synthesizes the work of economists and law and economics scholars in the field of public international law. The bulk of that work has been in the area of international trade, but many of the ideas in the trade literature have implications for other subfields. Recent years have seen a significant increase in research on other topics as well. The paper begins with a general framework for thinking about the positive and normative economics of public international law, and then proceeds to a treatment of specific topics including customary law, strategic alliances and the laws of war, international trade, international investment, international antitrust, human rights law, conflicts of law, and the international commons (fisheries). 1. Introduction International law has been recognized as a distinct field of study within the legal academy for well over a century, but economically-oriented scholars have paid it relatively little attention. Dunoff and Trachtman (1999). By far the bulk of the law and economics research in international law pertains to the law of international trade. Systematic work on other topics is limited at best, although research in the field generally is accelerating and the subject can properly be considered a growth area. The relative dearth of prior work, especially formal work, and its concentration on international trade issues, poses a number of challenges for a survey of this sort. An excessive emphasis on international trade will mask the richness and diversity of the field, and obscure rather than illuminate the potential research agenda. Moreover, large segments of the economic literature pertaining to international trade law already receive attention in the three volume Handbook of International Economics series, especially in Staiger (1995a), and in a number of other extant and forthcoming volumes focused on WTO issues including Bagwell and Staiger (2002) and Grossman and Helpman (2002). Accordingly, I have limited the treatment of trade issues in this chapter, emphasizing topics that illustrate broader themes for the economic analysis of international law. Much of the chapter will instead be devoted to a general framework for thinking about international law, along with brief discussions of a number of topics outside the realm of * Frank & Bernice Greenberg Professor of Law, University of Chicago. I have received thoughtful comments on an earlier draft from Kyle Bagwell, Eric Posner, Steven Shavell, and participants in the Handbook of Law and Economics conference at Stanford Law School

trade. with the understanding that an informal treatment is all that the existing literature has to offer on many of them Sections 2 and 3 of the chapter provide legal background on the field of international law, followed by a discussion of general economic considerations that cut across a range of possible topics. The analysis will encompass the various possible functions of international law, the challenges involved in realizing gains from international cooperation, the design and function of mechanisms for its enforcement, and the interface between domestic and international law. Sections 4-10 of the chapter consider particular topics, including strategic alliances and laws of war, international rade. international investment international antitrust. human rights law. conflicts of law and the international commons(fisheries) As a final, preliminary disclaimer, I have not undertaken to survey and incorporate the vast political science literature on public international law. Much of that literature is excellent, and the"rational choice literature in particular is often quite close in both spirit and method to the work of economists. I omit attention to it not because of any negative judgment about its quality, but to make the task at hand a manageable one Readers seeking a window into the rational choice perspective on international relations and institutions might wish to consult Snidal (1996)and(2002). Carlsnaes, Risse and Simmons(2002) provide a broader introduction to modern international relations work in political science 2. Legal background The field of international law is conventionally divided into two subfields: public"international law and"privateinternational law. "Public"international law refers to the body of law that governs relations between states or countries. " Private international law refers to the body of law that governs international relations between private citizens or companies. Most private international law relates to international b s transactions, and may be subsumed for analytic purposes under other topics such as contract law, corporate law and tax law that are the subject of other chapters the Handbook of Law and Economics. Accordingly, my focus in this chapter is almost exclusively on public international law. The genesis of public international law necessarily differs from that of domestic law. No international legislature exists to pass the equivalent of domestic statutes, and no international court exists with the power to create a general international common law Instead, public international law arises only by agreement among states

trade, with the understanding that an informal treatment is all that the existing literature has to offer on many of them. Sections 2 and 3 of the chapter provide legal background on the field of international law, followed by a discussion of general economic considerations that cut across a range of possible topics. The analysis will encompass the various possible functions of international law, the challenges involved in realizing gains from international cooperation, the design and function of mechanisms for its enforcement, and the interface between domestic and international law. Sections 4-10 of the chapter consider particular topics, including strategic alliances and laws of war, international trade, international investment, international antitrust, human rights law, conflicts of law, and the international commons (fisheries). As a final, preliminary disclaimer, I have not undertaken to survey and incorporate the vast political science literature on public international law. Much of that literature is excellent, and the “rational choice” literature in particular is often quite close in both spirit and method to the work of economists. I omit attention to it not because of any negative judgment about its quality, but to make the task at hand a manageable one. Readers seeking a window into the rational choice perspective on international relations and institutions might wish to consult Snidal (1996) and (2002). Carlsnaes, Risse and Simmons (2002) provide a broader introduction to modern international relations work in political science. 2. Legal Background The field of international law is conventionally divided into two subfields: “public” international law and “private” international law. “Public” international law refers to the body of law that governs relations between states or countries. “Private” international law refers to the body of law that governs international relations between private citizens or companies. Most private international law relates to international business transactions, and may be subsumed for analytic purposes under other topics such as contract law, corporate law and tax law that are the subject of other chapters in the Handbook of Law and Economics. Accordingly, my focus in this chapter is almost exclusively on public international law. The genesis of public international law necessarily differs from that of domestic law. No international legislature exists to pass the equivalent of domestic statutes, and no international court exists with the power to create a general international common law. Instead, public international law arises only by agreement among states

Often, agreement is manifest in an instrument known as a treaty. a treaty is an agreement executed by duly authorized officials of signatory states, evincing an intention to make it a binding legal obligation. Treaty obligations are themselves governed by over-arching treaty known as the Vienna Convention on Treaties, which supplies rules for their interpretation and enforcement. Note that the concept of a"treaty"is not necessarily the same in international and domestic law. The U.S. President, for example has the authority in many areas to bind the United States internationally through Executive Agreements, sometimes accompanied by formal Congressional approval and sometimes not. These agreements have the same status as treaties under international law even though they are not treaties under domestic law(which provides that treaties"must be approved by a two-thirds vote of the U. s. Senate) Agreement may also become manifest as customary international law, which is defined as ageneral and consistent practice of states followed by them from a sense of legal obligation. The traditional test for the emergence of customary law thus requires a high degree of consistency in state practice, and a belief that the practice has become a legal obligation. Both of these requirements are imprecise, and scholars often disagree about what practices have achieved the status of customary law. Some rules of customar international law are uncontroversial, however, such as those relating to aspects of diplomatic immunity. It is generally said that states may avoid an obligation to obey customary international law by"opting out" at an early stage of its evolution, but once they have manifested agreement with it through conforming behavior, any subsequent deviation is illegal International legal scholars also make reference to the concept of soft law. Soft law encompasses a range of things, including formal agreements that are understood not to be binding " under international law, as well as agreements that may be" binding" but that are essentially hortatory or aspirational. Examples of each abound-the Cuban Missile Crisis was settled by an informal agreement, for example, while numerous provisions in Wto treaty text encourage but do not require special trade treatment for developing countries The enforcement of international law to the extent that it is successful occurs in a variety of ways. The closest analog to the coercive enforcement powers often exercised by domestic courts is found in the United Nations. A serious breach of U N. obligation may result in the authorization of substantial sanctions by the Security Council, or in American Law Institute, Restatement(Third) of the Foreign Relations Law of the United States $102(2 (1987)

Often, agreement is manifest in an instrument known as a treaty. A treaty is an agreement executed by duly authorized officials of signatory states, evincing an intention to make it a binding legal obligation. Treaty obligations are themselves governed by an over-arching treaty known as the Vienna Convention on Treaties, which supplies rules for their interpretation and enforcement. Note that the concept of a “treaty” is not necessarily the same in international and domestic law. The U.S. President, for example, has the authority in many areas to bind the United States internationally through “Executive Agreements,” sometimes accompanied by formal Congressional approval and sometimes not. These agreements have the same status as treaties under international law, even though they are not treaties under domestic law (which provides that “treaties” must be approved by a two-thirds vote of the U.S. Senate). Agreement may also become manifest as customary international law, which is defined as a “general and consistent practice of states followed by them from a sense of legal obligation.”1 The traditional test for the emergence of customary law thus requires a high degree of consistency in state practice, and a belief that the practice has become a legal obligation. Both of these requirements are imprecise, and scholars often disagree about what practices have achieved the status of customary law. Some rules of customary international law are uncontroversial, however, such as those relating to aspects of diplomatic immunity. It is generally said that states may avoid an obligation to obey customary international law by “opting out” at an early stage of its evolution, but once they have manifested agreement with it through conforming behavior, any subsequent deviation is illegal. International legal scholars also make reference to the concept of “soft law.” Soft law encompasses a range of things, including formal agreements that are understood not to be “binding” under international law, as well as agreements that may be “binding” but that are essentially hortatory or aspirational. Examples of each abound—the Cuban Missile Crisis was settled by an informal agreement, for example, while numerous provisions in WTO treaty text encourage but do not require special trade treatment for developing countries. The enforcement of international law, to the extent that it is successful, occurs in a variety of ways. The closest analog to the coercive enforcement powers often exercised by domestic courts is found in the United Nations. A serious breach of U.N. obligations may result in the authorization of substantial sanctions by the Security Council, or in 1 American Law Institute, Restatement (Third) of the Foreign Relations Law of the United States §102(2) (1987)

extreme cases in a resolution authorizing the use of military force against the violator state. Much of international law falls outside the purview of U N. obligations, however, and thus outside its enforcement mechanism Some international legal regimes have their own tribunals with the power to adjudicate violations(such as NAFTa and the WTo), The International Court of Justice also has jurisdiction to hear a broad range of disputes The power to adjudicate disputes may or may not be accompanied by the power to authorize or impose sanctions however, and the nature of any sanctions may be tightly circumscribed. Formal sanctions for the violation of WTo obligations, for example, are limited to the withdrawal of benefits under Wto agreements. If international law is incorporated into domestic law, as quite often occurs, then the powers of domestic courts can be brought to bear on certain types of violations. This mechanism too has its limitations, as many international legal obligations are never incorporated into domestic law. Further, domestic courts are often limited in their jurisdiction to enforce international obligations that are so incorporated--principles of foreign sovereign immunity, for example, often insulate states from actions against them in foreign courts Finally, many international legal obligations exist as to which there is no formal enforcement or sanctioning mechanism at all Where some enforcement mechanism exists. a further issue arises as to who has standing to invoke it. Public international law governs relations among states and generally speaking, only states have standing to enforce it. Private citizens have no right pursue most claims under international law even if they have suffered substantial injury due to a violation. An important exception of sorts exists, however, if nations incorporate international law into their domestic legal systems. Private actors may ther be able rely on their access to domestic courts to enforce what originates as an international legal obligation. Finally, private citizens occasionally have standing to pursue claims before international tribunals, as in the case of the NAFTa investor rights provisions which allow investors access to NAFTA arbitration 3. Economic Aspects of International Law Public international law represents a number of distinct phenomena. Some"law' may be no more than a behavioral regularity in the practices of states, while other law may represent rules coercively imposed on less powerful states by more powerful states Still other types of law may arise to promote the domestic objectives of participating officials. But many of the more interesting and important pockets of international law may be seen as efforts to coordinate the behavior of states to address externalities. These

extreme cases in a resolution authorizing the use of military force against the violator state. Much of international law falls outside the purview of U.N. obligations, however, and thus outside its enforcement mechanism. Some international legal regimes have their own tribunals with the power to adjudicate violations (such as NAFTA and the WTO), The International Court of Justice also has jurisdiction to hear a broad range of disputes. The power to adjudicate disputes may or may not be accompanied by the power to authorize or impose sanctions, however, and the nature of any sanctions may be tightly circumscribed. Formal sanctions for the violation of WTO obligations, for example, are limited to the withdrawal of benefits under WTO agreements. If international law is incorporated into domestic law, as quite often occurs, then the powers of domestic courts can be brought to bear on certain types of violations. This mechanism too has its limitations, as many international legal obligations are never incorporated into domestic law. Further, domestic courts are often limited in their jurisdiction to enforce international obligations that are so incorporated—principles of foreign sovereign immunity, for example, often insulate states from actions against them in foreign courts. Finally, many international legal obligations exist as to which there is no formal enforcement or sanctioning mechanism at all. Where some enforcement mechanism exists, a further issue arises as to who has standing to invoke it. Public international law governs relations among states and, generally speaking, only states have standing to enforce it. Private citizens have no right to pursue most claims under international law even if they have suffered substantial injury due to a violation. An important exception of sorts exists, however, if nations incorporate international law into their domestic legal systems. Private actors may then be able rely on their access to domestic courts to enforce what originates as an international legal obligation. Finally, private citizens occasionally have standing to pursue claims before international tribunals, as in the case of the NAFTA investor rights provisions which allow investors access to NAFTA arbitration. 3. Economic Aspects of International Law Public international law represents a number of distinct phenomena. Some “law” may be no more than a behavioral regularity in the practices of states, while other law may represent rules coercively imposed on less powerful states by more powerful states. Still other types of law may arise to promote the domestic objectives of participating officials. But many of the more interesting and important pockets of international law may be seen as efforts to coordinate the behavior of states to address externalities. These

externalities may be nonpecuniary, the sort that produce inefficiency in competitive markets, or pecuniary, creating inefficiency due to an absence of competitive conditions In this section, I begin with some broad observations about the econom erspective on public international law. Because systematic discussions of international law often imagine that states behave as if they have"preferences, " the first topic concerns the conceptualization of states as rational actors. The analysis proceeds to a general discussion of customary international law, to a discussion of the economics of treaties, and finally to consideration of the interface between domestic and national law. A States as Rational Actors Positive economic analysis of international legal regimes conventionally proceeds from an assumption that states behave as if they are rational maximizers over some set of preferences regarding the outcomes of their interaction. The specific assumptions that may be made in this regard are myriad. States may be assumed to behave as economic welfare maximizers. or to maximize a social welfare function that weighs the welfare of certain constituencies more heavily than others. The preferences of the state"may be assumed to be those of its political leaders, who may maximize votes, campaign contributions, or their personal welfare. Innumerable other variations can be imagined depending on the context Whatever precise assumption is made about the nature of preferences, it common to embody a further assumption that states act as if they "care"primarily or exclusively about their own welfare or interests and less or not at all about the welfare ol interests of other states or their political leaders. A divergence will then arise between the national maximand and the global maximand e pr maximizers is surely somewhat simplistic. States represent an aggregation of many different actors, whose preferences may well be at odds. The actor with the power to choose among alternatives may change over time, and the constraints imposed on actors with the power to make choices can change over time(in the United States, think of the President as the actor with the power to make choices on international matters, subject to constraints imposed by Congress). Even when it is plausible to assume that a pertinent decisionmaker has a preference ordering over the available alternatives at a point in time therefore, the notion that the"preferences"of the state are stable over time, or that they obey potentially important regularity assumptions, may be quite problematic Although one must acknowledge this problem, there is often little to be done about it in a tractable modeling framework beyond remaining attentive to its possible

externalities may be nonpecuniary, the sort that produce inefficiency in competitive markets, or pecuniary, creating inefficiency due to an absence of competitive conditions. In this section, I begin with some broad observations about the economic perspective on public international law. Because systematic discussions of international law often imagine that states behave as if they have “preferences,” the first topic concerns the conceptualization of states as rational actors. The analysis proceeds to a general discussion of customary international law, to a discussion of the economics of treaties, and finally to consideration of the interface between domestic and national law. A. States as Rational Actors Positive economic analysis of international legal regimes conventionally proceeds from an assumption that states behave as if they are rational maximizers over some set of preferences regarding the outcomes of their interaction. The specific assumptions that may be made in this regard are myriad. States may be assumed to behave as economic welfare maximizers, or to maximize a social welfare function that weighs the welfare of certain constituencies more heavily than others. The preferences of the “state” may be assumed to be those of its political leaders, who may maximize votes, campaign contributions, or their personal welfare. Innumerable other variations can be imagined depending on the context. Whatever precise assumption is made about the nature of preferences, it is common to embody a further assumption that states act as if they “care” primarily or exclusively about their own welfare or interests, and less or not at all about the welfare or interests of other states or their political leaders. A divergence will then arise between the national maximand and the global maximand. The assumption that states have preference orderings and act as rational maximizers is surely somewhat simplistic. States represent an aggregation of many different actors, whose preferences may well be at odds. The actor with the power to choose among alternatives may change over time, and the constraints imposed on actors with the power to make choices can change over time (in the United States, think of the President as the actor with the power to make choices on international matters, subject to constraints imposed by Congress). Even when it is plausible to assume that a pertinent decisionmaker has a preference ordering over the available alternatives at a point in time, therefore, the notion that the “preferences” of the “state” are stable over time, or that they obey potentially important regularity assumptions, may be quite problematic. Although one must acknowledge this problem, there is often little to be done about it in a tractable modeling framework beyond remaining attentive to its possible

implications for each subject area. Such a framework proceeds in the tradition of other areas of economic analysis, which embrace their own simple assumptions about the objective functions of corporations, bureaucracies, and other large institutions. Here In those other areas the test is not whether the assumptions are fully descriptive of behavior, but whether they yield useful insights with empirical purchase Economic analysis of international law also has its normative side of course, which rests on assumptions about what states ought to be maximizing. Once again,a variety of possible objective functions might be assumed, although the conventional measure of economic welfare is often employed B. The Economics of Customary International Law and"Soft"Law A great deal of work has been done on the economics of"custom' in various contexts. Commentators have written about the of custom evidence to prove negligence in tort actions, the use of customary business practices as a basis for default rules in contract law, the efficiency of social norms, and the general phenomenon of order without lawin primitive or frontier societies. Such topics receive significant attention in other chapters in this Handbook Despite the attention to custom in other contexts, very little has been written about customary international law from an economic perspective. The most notable exception is Goldsmith Posner(1999& 2004) Recall the standard characterization of customary international law: it emerges when there is a high degree of convergence in the practice of states, and a belief that adherence to the practice has become a legal obligation. The latter requirement is know as opinio juris and is central to the existence of customary law according to traditional doctrine. Mere regularities in state behavior, without opinio juris, are not law. Goldsmith and Posner contend that this description of customary international law is largely incoherent. Their alternative theory begins by offering a positive theory of convergence is state practice, which they suggest may result from four distinct phenomena. The first is simple coincidence of interest, whereby all states behave the same way because it is in their unilateral interest regardless of the choices made by other states. They offer" ambassadorial immunity as a possible example(although this subject is governed by treaty as well as custom in modern times)states may protect the ambassadors of other states. even in times of conflict with them because the ambassadors perform a valuable function in facilitating communication with other governments. A second explanation for convergence of practice is pure coercion. Here, they suggest that

implications for each subject area. Such a framework proceeds in the tradition of other areas of economic analysis, which embrace their own simple assumptions about the objective functions of corporations, bureaucracies, and other large institutions. Here, as in those other areas, the test is not whether the assumptions are fully descriptive of behavior, but whether they yield useful insights with empirical purchase. Economic analysis of international law also has its normative side, of course, which rests on assumptions about what states ought to be maximizing. Once again, a variety of possible objective functions might be assumed, although the conventional measure of economic welfare is often employed. B. The Economics of Customary International Law and “Soft” Law A great deal of work has been done on the economics of “custom” in various contexts. Commentators have written about the use of custom evidence to prove negligence in tort actions, the use of customary business practices as a basis for default rules in contract law, the efficiency of social norms, and the general phenomenon of “order without law” in primitive or frontier societies. Such topics receive significant attention in other chapters in this Handbook. Despite the attention to custom in other contexts, very little has been written about customary international law from an economic perspective. The most notable exception is Goldsmith & Posner (1999 & 2004). Recall the standard characterization of customary international law: it emerges when there is a high degree of convergence in the practice of states, and a belief that adherence to the practice has become a legal obligation. The latter requirement is know as opinio juris and is central to the existence of customary law according to traditional doctrine. Mere regularities in state behavior, without opinio juris, are not law. Goldsmith and Posner contend that this description of customary international law is largely incoherent. Their alternative theory begins by offering a positive theory of convergence is state practice, which they suggest may result from four distinct phenomena. The first is simple coincidence of interest, whereby all states behave the same way because it is in their unilateral interest regardless of the choices made by other states. They offer “ambassadorial immunity” as a possible example (although this subject is governed by treaty as well as custom in modern times)—states may protect the ambassadors of other states, even in times of conflict with them, because the ambassadors perform a valuable function in facilitating communication with other governments. A second explanation for convergence of practice is pure coercion. Here, they suggest that

the custom of"free ships, free goods, " whereby all property on neutral ships is immune from seizure (including enemy property ) is at times illustrative--powerful states may espect the principle because the seizure of neutral ships to capture enemy property is not worth the bother, while weaker states may respect the principle for fear of retaliation by powerful states. The third possible reason for convergence arises when a common practice represents the solution to an iterated Prisoners Dilemma, which can be sustained over time by states with open-ended time horizons and sufficiently low discount rates They again offer ambassadorial immunity as a possible illustration, suggesting that an exc ange of ambassadors amounts to an exchange of hostages, and that the prospect o retaliatory acts against ones own ambassador can dissuade any temptation to interfere with the ambassadors of others. Finally, convergence may arise in the face of a pure coordination problem or otherwise where a"focal point is useful. They suggest that the convergence on a three-mile limit for territorial waters is an example here. For a variety of reasons including security, nations have an interest in claiming dominion over waters along their coast but the exact limits of territorial waters is to a degree a matter of indifference--a three mile limit supplies a focal point that all nations can accept In short, Goldsmith and Posner argue that convergence in state practice occurs for reasons of pure national self interest, albeit not the same reason every time. They further suggest that continued adherence to customary practice happens because the self- interested reasons for convergence remain in place, not because of any independent sense of legal obligation. Opinio juris, they suggest, is a fiction, and what legal scholars refer to law"" is really no more than a descriptive account of certain regularities in the behavior of states To bolster this latter claim goldsmith and posner document how ostensible rules of customary law are frequently violated when states have an interest in deviating. They further illustrate how rogue states, which they suggest have shorter time horizons and higher discount rates, are more likely to deviate than others. Because historical violations and breakdowns of custom can be linked to self-interested reasons for them Goldsmith and Posner find anecdotal empirical support for the claim that customary practices are mere regularities of self-interest, and that customary law per se exerts no tug on state behavior The proposition that customary international law'" generally emerges from the self-interested interaction of states, and that it promotes with their mutual interest for one reason or another, seems rather unremarkable. It would indeed be odd if a customary practice emerged on a large scale that made its adherents worse off over an extended period of time. While this aspect of Goldsmith and Posner's analysis seems compelling,a

the custom of “free ships, free goods,” whereby all property on neutral ships is immune from seizure (including enemy property), is at times illustrative—powerful states may respect the principle because the seizure of neutral ships to capture enemy property is not worth the bother, while weaker states may respect the principle for fear of retaliation by powerful states. The third possible reason for convergence arises when a common practice represents the solution to an iterated Prisoner’s Dilemma, which can be sustained over time by states with open-ended time horizons and sufficiently low discount rates. They again offer ambassadorial immunity as a possible illustration, suggesting that an exchange of ambassadors amounts to an exchange of hostages, and that the prospect of retaliatory acts against ones own ambassador can dissuade any temptation to interfere with the ambassadors of others. Finally, convergence may arise in the face of a pure coordination problem or otherwise where a “focal point” is useful. They suggest that the convergence on a three-mile limit for territorial waters is an example here. For a variety of reasons including security, nations have an interest in claiming dominion over waters along their coast, but the exact limits of territorial waters is to a degree a matter of indifference—a three mile limit supplies a focal point that all nations can accept. In short, Goldsmith and Posner argue that convergence in state practice occurs for reasons of pure national self interest, albeit not the same reason every time. They further suggest that continued adherence to customary practice happens because the self￾interested reasons for convergence remain in place, not because of any independent sense of legal obligation. Opinio juris, they suggest, is a fiction, and what legal scholars refer to as customary “law” is really no more than a descriptive account of certain regularities in the behavior of states. To bolster this latter claim, Goldsmith and Posner document how ostensible rules of customary law are frequently violated when states have an interest in deviating. They further illustrate how rogue states, which they suggest have shorter time horizons and higher discount rates, are more likely to deviate than others. Because historical violations and breakdowns of custom can be linked to self-interested reasons for them, Goldsmith and Posner find anecdotal empirical support for the claim that customary practices are mere regularities of self-interest, and that customary law per se exerts no tug on state behavior. The proposition that “customary international law” generally emerges from the self-interested interaction of states, and that it promotes with their mutual interest for one reason or another, seems rather unremarkable. It would indeed be odd if a customary practice emerged on a large scale that made its adherents worse off over an extended period of time. While this aspect of Goldsmith and Posner’s analysis seems compelling, a

skeptic might argue that they have not fully made their case on the nonexistence of opinio juris. Even if customary international law had some force of its own quite apart from the narrow self-interest of a state regarding a particular custom, one might still observe the same anecdotal bits of evidence that Goldsmith and Posner catalog. Nations might still deviate when their self-interested reasons were strong enough, for exampl and rogue states might still be the most likely to deviate. All that would be required is that the behavioral force of opinio juris be limited, so that counter-incentives of sufficient strength could override it. Thus, although Goldsmith and Posner are surely right that the traditional scholars cannot prove the existence of opinio juris by pointing to conformity with custom, neither can the detractors of the traditional view prove its nonexistence merely by pointing to self-interested deviations from custom If the empirical evidence is inconclusive, it remains to ask whether opinio juris can be given any theoretical content. Why would states feel any obligation to observe a custom that is no longer in their self interest? Traditional international law scholars suggest that once a practice becomes law, it infuses the morality of national bureaucrats, who then feel a sense of obligation to obey it. One might restate the proposition as a suggestion that"law" has expressive force and alters the preferences of pertinent national actors, leading them to prefer to obey it(or that they simply have an exogenous preference to obey all" law. )The difficulty with this account, as even noneconomic scholars have noted, is its circularity. Law exists only after the sense of legal obligation arises according to the definition of customary law, yet the sense of legal obligation is said on this account to follow after the emergence of" law a possible alternative account is suggested by Guzman(2002), who relies on the idea that violations of international law may damage a state's reputation. He suggests that international strategic interaction on narrow issues is generally embedded within a larger games, and that players' willingness to cooperate with other players on current issues may then turn on whether a player has developed a reputation for cooperation in the past. Under the usual assumptions that prevent backwards unraveling of cooperation (an infinite or open-ended time horizon) and that limit the short terms gains from defection(such as a low discount rate), Guzman argues that reputational considerations ne possibility of an equilibrium in which mutual cooperation is sustained over time in what might otherwise appear to be a one-shot game with defection as the Nash outcome The addition of reputation to the analysis suggests a possible economic interpretation of opinio juris. One might define it simply as a tendency to obey customary law due to the damage that defection does to a state's reputation as a cooperator, costs

skeptic might argue that they have not fully made their case on the nonexistence of opinio juris. Even if customary international law had some force of its own quite apart from the narrow self-interest of a state regarding a particular custom, one might still observe the same anecdotal bits of evidence that Goldsmith and Posner catalog. Nations might still deviate when their self-interested reasons were strong enough, for example, and rogue states might still be the most likely to deviate. All that would be required is that the behavioral force of opinio juris be limited, so that counter-incentives of sufficient strength could override it. Thus, although Goldsmith and Posner are surely right that the traditional scholars cannot prove the existence of opinio juris by pointing to conformity with custom, neither can the detractors of the traditional view prove its nonexistence merely by pointing to self-interested deviations from custom. If the empirical evidence is inconclusive, it remains to ask whether opinio juris can be given any theoretical content. Why would states feel any obligation to observe a custom that is no longer in their self interest? Traditional international law scholars suggest that once a practice becomes “law,” it infuses the morality of national bureaucrats, who then feel a sense of obligation to obey it. One might restate the proposition as a suggestion that “law” has expressive force and alters the preferences of pertinent national actors, leading them to prefer to obey it (or that they simply have an exogenous preference to obey all “law.”) The difficulty with this account, as even noneconomic scholars have noted, is its circularity. Law exists only after the sense of legal obligation arises according to the definition of customary law, yet the sense of legal obligation is said on this account to follow after the emergence of “law.” A possible alternative account is suggested by Guzman (2002), who relies on the idea that violations of international law may damage a state’s reputation. He suggests that international strategic interaction on narrow issues is generally embedded within a larger games, and that players’ willingness to cooperate with other players on current issues may then turn on whether a player has developed a reputation for cooperation in the past. Under the usual assumptions that prevent backwards unraveling of cooperation (an infinite or open-ended time horizon) and that limit the short terms gains from defection (such as a low discount rate), Guzman argues that reputational considerations create the possibility of an equilibrium in which mutual cooperation is sustained over time in what might otherwise appear to be a one-shot game with defection as the Nash outcome. The addition of reputation to the analysis suggests a possible economic interpretation of opinio juris. One might define it simply as a tendency to obey customary law due to the damage that defection does to a state’s reputation as a cooperator, costs

that are incurred not in the simple game in which defection is contemplated but in al Traditional international law scholars will find little solace in the reputational interpretation of opinio juris, however, because concern for reputation is no less self- interested than concern for payoffs in a narrower strategic interaction. Further, reputational considerations may be of minimal significance as a practical matter in many settings as both Goldsmith and Posner and Guzman argue. This general issue receives further attention below Aside from its examination of opinio juris, the law and economics literature makes a number of other useful points about the role of customary law. The commentators seem to agree that the ability of customary international law to orchestrate cooperation is limited to narrow circumstances. Problems that require complicated solutions are unlikely to be solved by implicit cooperation express negotiation and communication will probably be necessary. Further, problems that require the simultaneous cooperation of large numbers of nations will also be difficult to solve because of free rider problems in the enforcement mechanism. Even when a practice appears "customary"on a global scale, therefore, and is thought to represent mutual hat it is usuall than a recurring regul bilateral interaction Guzman makes the further point that if reputation is what creates some"force of law, then there is no reason to limit our conception of" to customary international law and treaties. Reputational concerns may be quite important to a world leader who gives her word to another, whether or not it is done in any formal fashion and whether or not it concerns some practice that is widespread in the international community. The raditional line between"hard law"(binding treaties and customary law) on the one hand and"soft law"(such as informal agreements and statements of intention) on the other may thus be quite misleading. Depending on context, states may be considerably more likely to comply with soft law than with hard law, and there is no reason to think that hard law is always preferable for orchestrating cooperation In short, economic thinking about customary international law calls into question the very meaning of the concept. It suggests that practices termed"lawin various interaction between states facing similar problems. The codification of customary law merely serves to publicize focal points, and to write down the rules of any game to facilitate future adherence to them. The capacity of customary"law to solve important problems that require cooperation or coordination is quite limited, and will tend to be

that are incurred not in the simple game in which defection is contemplated but in all other games where reputation affects the strategies played by other states. Traditional international law scholars will find little solace in the reputational interpretation of opinio juris, however, because concern for reputation is no less self￾interested than concern for payoffs in a narrower strategic interaction. Further, reputational considerations may be of minimal significance as a practical matter in many settings as both Goldsmith and Posner and Guzman argue. This general issue receives further attention below. Aside from its examination of opinio juris, the law and economics literature makes a number of other useful points about the role of customary law. The commentators seem to agree that the ability of customary international law to orchestrate cooperation is limited to narrow circumstances. Problems that require complicated solutions are unlikely to be solved by implicit cooperation—express negotiation and communication will probably be necessary. Further, problems that require the simultaneous cooperation of large numbers of nations will also be difficult to solve because of free rider problems in the enforcement mechanism. Even when a practice appears “customary” on a global scale, therefore, and is thought to represent mutual cooperation, the suggestion is that it is usually no more than a recurring regularity of bilateral interaction. Guzman makes the further point that if reputation is what creates some “force of law,” then there is no reason to limit our conception of “law” to customary international law and treaties. Reputational concerns may be quite important to a world leader who gives her word to another, whether or not it is done in any formal fashion and whether or not it concerns some practice that is widespread in the international community. The traditional line between “hard law” (binding treaties and customary law) on the one hand and “soft law” (such as informal agreements and statements of intention) on the other may thus be quite misleading. Depending on context, states may be considerably more likely to comply with soft law than with hard law, and there is no reason to think that hard law is always preferable for orchestrating cooperation. In short, economic thinking about customary international law calls into question the very meaning of the concept. It suggests that practices termed “law” in various quarters are no more that behavioral regularities that emerge from self-interested interaction between states facing similar problems. The codification of customary law merely serves to publicize focal points, and to write down the rules of any game to facilitate future adherence to them. The capacity of customary “law” to solve important problems that require cooperation or coordination is quite limited, and will tend to be

点击下载完整版文档(PDF)VIP每日下载上限内不扣除下载券和下载次数;
按次数下载不扣除下载券;
24小时内重复下载只扣除一次;
顺序:VIP每日次数-->可用次数-->下载券;
共81页,可试读20页,点击继续阅读 ↓↓
相关文档

关于我们|帮助中心|下载说明|相关软件|意见反馈|联系我们

Copyright © 2008-现在 cucdc.com 高等教育资讯网 版权所有