当前位置:高等教育资讯网  >  中国高校课件下载中心  >  大学文库  >  浏览文档

《法学基础理论》学习资料:The Problem of Social Cost

资源类别:文库,文档格式:PDF,文档页数:45,文件大小:1.46MB,团购合买
点击下载完整版文档(PDF)

CHICAGO JOURNALS The Problem of social Cost Author(s):R H. Coase Source: Journal of Law and Economics, Vol 3(Oct, 1960), pp. 1-44 Published by: The University of Chicago Press StableUrl:http://www.jstor.org/stable/724810 Accessed:22/03/200905:41 Your use of the jStOR archive indicates your acceptance of jSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jspJstOr'sTermsandConditionsofUseprovidesinpartthatunless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you ay use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showpublisher?publishercode=ucpress Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed of such transmission JStOR is a not-for-profit organization founded in 1995 to build trusted digital archives for scholarship. We work with the holarly community to preserve their work and the materials they rely upon, and to build a common research platform that promotes the discovery and use of these resources. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor. org The University of Chicago Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Journal of ittp://www.jstor.org

The Problem of Social Cost Author(s): R. H. Coase Source: Journal of Law and Economics, Vol. 3 (Oct., 1960), pp. 1-44 Published by: The University of Chicago Press Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/724810 Accessed: 22/03/2009 05:41 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=ucpress. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit organization founded in 1995 to build trusted digital archives for scholarship. We work with the scholarly community to preserve their work and the materials they rely upon, and to build a common research platform that promotes the discovery and use of these resources. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. The University of Chicago Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Journal of Law and Economics. http://www.jstor.org

h e durna LAW O ECONOMICS ⅴ OLUME I OCTOBER 1960 THE PROBLEM OF SOCIAL COST R. H. COASE I. THE PROBLEM To bE ExAMINED1 HIs paper is concerned with those actions of business firms which have harmful effects on others. The standard example is that of a factory the smoke from which has harmful effects on those occupying neighbouring properties The economic analysis of such a situation has usually proceeded in terms of a divergence between the private and social product of the far ory, in which economists have largely followed the treatment of Pigou in The Economics of Welfare. The conclusions to which this kind of analy is seems to have led most economists is that it would be desirable to make the owner of the factory liable for the damage caused to those injured by the smoke, or alternatively, to place a tax on the factory owner varying with the amount of smoke pro- duced and equivalent in money terms to the damage it would cause, or finally, to exclude the factory from residential districts (and presumably from other 1 This article, although concerned with a technical problem of economic analysis, arose ut of the study of the Political Economy of Broadcasting which I am he argument of the present article was implicit in a previous article roblem of allocating radio and television frequencies (The Federal Communication ommission, 2 J. Law& Econ. [1959])but comments which I have received seemed to uggest that it would be desirable to deal with the question in without reference to the original problem for the solution of which the analysis was de-

The Journal of LAW c ECONOMICS VOLUME III OCTOBER 1960 THE PROBLEM OF SOCIAL COST R. H. COASE University of Virginia I. THE PROBLEM TO BE EXAMINED1 THIS paper is concerned with those actions of business firms which have harmful effects on others. The standard example is that of a factory the smoke from which has harmful effects on those occupying neighbouring properties. The economic analysis of such a situation has usually proceeded in terms of a divergence between the private and social product of the fartory, in which economists have largely followed the treatment of Pigou in The Economics of Welfare. The conclusions to which this kind of analy?is seems to have led most economists is that it would be desirable to make the owner of the factory liable for the damage caused to those injured by the smoke, or alternatively, to place a tax on the factory owner varying with the amount of smoke pro￾duced and equivalent in money terms to the damage it would cause, or finally, to exclude the factory from residential districts (and presumably from other 1 This article, although concerned with a technical problem of economic analysis, arose out of the study of the Political Economy of Broadcasting which I am now conducting. The argument of the present article was implicit in a previous article dealing with the problem of allocating radio and television frequencies (The Federal Communications Commission, 2 J. Law & Econ. [1959]) but comments which I have received seemed to suggest that it would be desirable to deal with the question in a more explicit way and without reference to the original problem for the solution of which the analysis was de￾veloped

THE JOURNAL OF LAW AND ECONOMICS areas in which the emission of smoke would have harmful effects on others) It is my contention that the suggested courses of action are inappropriate, in that they lead to results which are not necessarily, or even usually, desirable I. THE RECIPROCAL NATURE OF THE PROBLEM The traditional approach has tended to obscure the nature of the choice that has to be made The question is commonly thought of as one in which a inflicts harm on b and what has to be decided is: how should we restrain A? But this is wrong. We are dealing with a problem of a reciprocal nature. To avoid the harm to B would inflict harm on A. The real question that has to be decided is: should A be allowed to harm b or should b be allowed to harm a? The problem is to avoid the more serious harm. I instanced in my previous article2 the case of a confectioner the noise and vibrations from whose ma chinery disturbed a doctor in his work. To avoid harming the doctor would inflict harm on the confectioner. The problem posed by this case was essential- ly whether it was worth while, as a result of restricting the methods of produc tion which could be used by the confectioner to secure more doctoring at the cost of a reduced supply of confectionery products. Another example is forded by the problem of straying cattle which destroy crops on neighbour ing land. If it is inevitable that some cattle will stray, an increase in the sup ply of meat can only be obtained at the expense of a decrease in the supply of crops. The nature of the choice is clear: meat or crops. What answer should be given is, of course, not clear unless we know the value of what is obtained as well as the value of what is sacrificed to obtain it. To give another example, Professor George J. Stigler instances the contamination of a stream. assume that the harmful effect of the pollution is that it kills the question to be decided is: is the value of the fish lost greater or less value of the product which the contamination of the stream makes possible It goes almost without saying that this problem has to be looked at in total and at the marg III. THE PRICING SYSTEM WITH LIABILITY FOR DAMAGE i propose to start my analysis by examining a case in which most econo mists would presumably agree that the problem would be solved in a com pletely satisfactory manner: when the damaging business has to pay for all damage caused and the pricing system works smoothly(strictly this means hat the operation of a pricing system is without cost) a good example of the problem under discussion is afforded by the case of straying cattle which destroy crops growing on neighbouring land. Let us sup- pose that a farmer and a cattle-raiser are operating on neighbouring proper 2 Coase, The Federal Communications Commission, 2 J. Law Econ 26-27(1959) G.J. Stigler, The Theory of Price 105 (1952)

2 THE JOURNAL OF LAW AND ECONOMICS areas in which the emission of smoke would have harmful effects on others). It is my contention that the suggested courses of action are inappropriate, in that they lead to results which are not necessarily, or even usually, desirable. II. THE RECIPROCAL NATURE OF THE PROBLEM The traditional approach has tended to obscure the nature of the choice that has to be made. The question is commonly thought of as one in which A inflicts harm on B and what has to be decided is: how should we restrain A? But this is wrong. We are dealing with a problem of a reciprocal nature. To avoid the harm to B would inflict harm on A. The real question that has to be decided is: should A be allowed to harm B or should B be allowed to harm A? The problem is to avoid the more serious harm. I instanced in my previous article2 the case of a confectioner the noise and vibrations from whose ma￾chinery disturbed a doctor in his work. To avoid harming the doctor would inflict harm on the confectioner. The problem posed by this case was essential￾ly whether it was worth while, as a result of restricting the methods of produc￾tion which could be used by the confectioner, to secure more doctoring at the cost of a reduced supply of confectionery products. Another example is afforded by the problem of straying cattle which destroy crops on neighbour￾ing land. If it is inevitable that some cattle will stray, an increase in the sup￾ply of meat can only be obtained at the expense of a decrease in the supply of crops. The nature of the choice is clear: meat or crops. What answer should be given is, of course, not clear unless we know the value of what is obtained as well as the value of what is sacrificed to obtain it. To give another example, Professor George J. Stigler instances the contamination of a stream.3 If we assume that the harmful effect of the pollution is that it kills the fish, the question to be decided is: is the value of the fish lost greater or less than the value of the product which the contamination of the stream makes possible. It goes almost without saying that this problem has to be looked at in total and at the margin. III. THE PRICING SYSTEM WITH LIABILITY FOR DAMAGE I propose to start my analysis by examining a case in which most econo￾mists would presumably agree that the problem would be solved in a com￾pletely satisfactory manner: when the damaging business has to pay for all damage caused and the pricing system works smoothly (strictly this means that the operation of a pricing system is without cost). A good example of the problem under discussion is afforded by the case of straying cattle which destroy crops growing on neighbouring land. Let us sup￾pose that a farmer and a cattle-raiser are operating on neighbouring proper- 2 Coase, The Federal Communications Commission, 2 J. Law & Econ. 26-27 (1959). 3 G. J. Stigler, The Theory of Price 105 (1952)

THE PROBLEM OF SOCIAL COST ties. Let us further suppose that, without any fencing between the properties, an increase in the size of the cattle-raiser's herd increases the total damage to the farmers crops. What happens to the marginal damage as the size of the herd increases is another matter This depends on whether the cattle tend to follow one another or to roam side by side, on whether they tend to be more or less restless as the size of the herd increases and on other similar factors. For my immediate purpose, it is immaterial what assumption is made about marginal damage as the size of the herd increases. To simplify the argument, i propose to use an arithmetical example I shall assume that the annual cost of fencing the farmers property is $9 and that the price of the crop is $1 per ton i assume that the relation between the number of cattle in the herd and the annual crop loss is as follows Number in Herd Annual Crop Loss Crop Loss per Additional Given that the cattle-raiser is liable for the damage caused the additional annual cost imposed on the cattle-raiser if he increased his herd from, say, 2 to 3 steers is $3 and in deciding on the size of the herd, he will take this into account along with his other costs. That is, he will not increase the size of the herd unless the value of the additional meat produced (assuming that the cattle-raiser slaughters the cattle), is greater than the additional costs that this will entail, including the value of the additional crops destroyed. Of course, if, by the employment of dogs, herdsmen, aeroplanes, mobile radio and ther means, the amount of damage can be reduced, these means will be adopted when their cost is less than the value of the crop which they prevent being lost. Given that the annual cost of fencing is $9 the cattle-raiser who wished to have a herd with 4 steers or more would pay for fencing to be erected and maintained assuming that other means of attaining the same end would not do so more cheaply. when the fence is erected the marginal cost lue to the liability for damage becomes zero, except to the extent that an increase in the size of the herd necessitates a stronger and therefore more expensive fence because more steers are liable to lean against it at the same time. But, of course, it may be cheaper for the cattle-raiser not to fence and to pay for the damaged crops, as in my arithmetical example, with 3 or fewer steers It might be thought that the fact that the cattle-raiser would pay for all crops damaged would lead the farmer to increase his planting if a cattle-raiser ame to occupy the neighbouring property. But this is not so. If the crop was previously sold in conditions of perfect competition, marginal cost was equal

THE PROBLEM OF SOCIAL COST 3 ties. Let us further suppose that, without any fencing between the properties, an increase in the size of the cattle-raiser's herd increases the total damage to the farmer's crops. What happens to the marginal damage as the size of the herd increases is another matter. This depends on whether the cattle tend to follow one another or to roam side by side, on whether they tend to be more or less restless as the size of the herd increases and on other similar factors. For my immediate purpose, it is immaterial what assumption is made about marginal damage as the size of the herd increases. To simplify the argument, I propose to use an arithmetical example. I shall assume that the annual cost of fencing the farmer's property is $9 and that the price of the crop is $1 per ton. Also, I assume that the relation between the number of cattle in the herd and the annual crop loss is as follows: Number in Herd Annual Crop Loss Crop Loss per Additional (Steers) (Tons) Steer (Tons) 1 1 1 2 3 2 3 6 3 4 ! 0 4 Given that the cattle.raiser is liable for the damage caused, the additional annual cost imposed on the cattle-raiser if he increased his herd from, say, 2 to 3 steers is $3 and in deciding on the size of the herd, he will take this into account along with his other costs. That is, he will not increase the size of the herd unless the value of the additional meat produced (assuming that the cattle-raiser slaughters the cattle), is greater than the additional costs that this will entail, including the value of the additional crops destroyed. Of course, if, by the employment of dogs, herdsmen, aeroplanes, mobile radio and other means, the amount of damage can be reduced, these means will be adopted when their cost is less than the value of the crop which they prevent being lost. Given that the annual cost of fencing is $9, the cattle-raiser who wished to have a herd with 4 steers or more would pay for fencing to be erected and maintained, assuming that other means of attaining the same end would not do so more cheaply. When the fence is erected, the marginal cost due to the liability for damage becomes zero, except to the extent that an increase in the size of the herd necessitates a stronger and therefore more expensive fence because more steers are liable to lean against it at the same time. But, of course, it may be cheaper for the cattle-raiser not to fence and to pay for the damaged crops, as in my arithmetical example, with 3 or fewer steers. It might be thought that the fact that the cattle-raiser would pay for all crops damaged would lead the farmer to increase his planting if a cattle-raiser came to occupy the neighbouring property. But this is not so. If the crop was previously sold in conditions of perfect competition, marginal cost was equal

THE JOURNAL OF LAW AND ECONOMICS to price for the amount of planting undertaken and any expansion would have reduced the profits of the farmer. In the new situation, the existence of crop damage would mean that the farmer would sell less on the open market but his receipts for a given production would remain the same, since the cattle Of if cattI aising commonly involved the destruction of crops, the coming into existence of a cattle- raising industry might raise the price of the crops involved and farmers would then extend their planting. But i wish to confine my attention to the individual farmer I have said that the occupation of a neighbouring property by a cattle wiser would not cause the amount of production, or perhaps more exactly the amount of planting, by the farmer to increase. In fact, if the cattle-raising has any effect, it will be to decrease the amount of planting. The reason for this is that, for any given tract of land, if the value of the crop damaged is so great that the receipts from the sale of the undamaged crop are less than the total costs of cultivating that tract of land, it will be profitable for the farmer and the cattle-raiser to make a bargain whereby that tract of land is left un cultivated. This can be made clear by means of an arithmetical example Assume initially that the value of the crop obtained from cultivating a given tract of land is $12 and that the cost incurred in cultivating this tract of land is $10, the net gain from cultivating the land being $2. I assume for purposes of simplicity that the farmer owns the land. Now assume that the cattle- raiser starts operations on the neighbouring property and that the value of the crops damaged is $1. In this case $11 is obtained by the farmer from sale on he market and $1 is obtained from the cattle-raiser for damage suffered and the net gain remains $2. Now suppose that the cattle-raiser finds it profitable to increase the size of his herd, even though the amount of damage rises to $3 which means that the value of the additional meat production is greater than the additional costs, including the additional $2 payment for damage. But the total payment for damage is now $3. The net gain to the farmer from cultivat ing the land is still $2. The cattle-raiser would be better off if the farmer would agree not to cultivate his land for any payment less than $3. The farmer would be agreeable to not cultivating the land for any payment greater than $2. There is clearly room for a mutually satisfactory bargain which would lead to the abandonment of cultivation But the same argument applies not only to the whole tract cultivated by the farmer but also to any d on the assumption that the alternative to cultivation of the crop is abandonment of cultivation altogether. But this need not be so There may be crops which are less liable to damage by cattle but which would not profitable as the crop grown in the absence of damage. Thus, if the cultivation of a new r of $1 instead of $2, and the size of the herd whicl with the old crop would cause $1 damage with the new crop, it ould be profitable to the cattle-raiser to pay any sum less than $2 to induce the farmer

4 THE JOURNAL OF LAW AND ECONOMICS to price for the amount of planting undertaken and any expansion would have reduced the profits of the farmer. In the new situation, the existence of crop damage would mean that the farmer would sell less on the open market but his receipts for a given production would remain the same, since the cattle￾raiser would pay the market price for any crop damaged. Of course, if cattle￾raising commonly involved the destruction of crops, the coming into existence of a cattle-raising industry might raise the price of the crops involved and farmers would then extend their planting. But I wish to confine my attention to the individual farmer. I have said that the occupation of a neighbouring property by a cattle￾raiser would not cause the amount of production, or perhaps more exactly the amount of planting, by the farmer to increase. In fact, if the cattle-raising has any effect, it will be to decrease the amount of planting. The reason for this is that, for any given tract of land, if the value of the crop damaged is so great that the receipts from the sale of the undamaged crop are less than the total costs of cultivating that tract of land, it will be profitable for the farmer and the cattle-raiser to make a bargain whereby that tract of land is left un￾cultivated. This can be made clear by means of an arithmetical example. Assume initially that the value of the crop obtained from cultivating a given tract of land is $12 and that the cost incurred in cultivating this tract of land is $10, the net gain from cultivating the land being $2. I assume for purposes of simplicity that the farmer owns the land. Now assume that the cattle￾raiser starts operations on the neighbouring property and that the value of the crops damaged is $1. In this case $11 is obtained by the farmer from sale on the market and $1 is obtained from the cattle-raiser for damage suffered and the net gain remains $2. Now suppose that the cattle-raiser finds it profitable to increase the size of his herd, even though the amount of damage rises to $3; which means that the value of the additional meat production is greater than the additional costs, including the additional $2 payment for damage. But the total payment for damage is now $3. The net gain to the farmer from cultivat￾ing the land is still $2. The cattle-raiser would be better off if the farmer would agree not to cultivate his land for any payment less than $3. The farmer would be agreeable to not cultivating the land for any payment greater than $2. There is clearly room for a mutually satisfactory bargain which would lead to the abandonment of cultivation.4 But the same argument applies not only to the whole tract cultivated by the farmer but also to any 'The argument in the text has proceeded on the assumption that the alternative to cultivation of the crop is abandonment of cultivation altogether. But this need not be so. There may be crops which are less liable to damage by cattle but which would not be as profitable as the crop grown in the absence of damage. Thus, if the cultivation of a new crop would yield a return to the farmer of $1 instead of $2, and the size of the herd which would cause $3 damage with the old crop would cause $1 damage with the new crop, it would be profitable to the cattle-raiser to pay any sum less than $2 to induce the farmer

THE PROBLEM OF SOCIAL COST subdivision of it. Suppose, for example, that the cattle have a well-defined route, say, to a brook or to a shady area. In these circumstances, the amount of damage to the crop along the route may well be great and if so, it could be that the farmer and the cattle- raiser would find it profitable to make a bargain whereby the farmer would agree not to cultivate this strip of land But this raises a further possibility. Suppose that there is such a well defined route Suppose further that the value of the crop that would be ob- tained by cultivating this strip of land is $10 but that the cost of cultivation is $11. In the absence of the cattle-raiser, the land would not be cultivated However, given the presence of the cattle- raiser, it could well be that if the strip was cultivated, the whole crop would be destroyed by the cattle. In which case, the cattle-raiser would be forced to pay $10 to the farmer. It is true that the farmer would lose $1. But the cattle raiser would lose $10. Clear- ly this is a situation which is not likely to last indefinitely since neither party would want this to happen. The aim of the farmer would be to induce the cattle-raiser to make a payment in return for an agreement to leave this land ultivated. The farmer would not be able to obtain a payment greater than the cost of fencing off this piece of land nor so high as to lead the cattle- raiser to abandon the use of the neighbouring property. What payment would in fact be made would depend on the shrewdness of the farmer and the cattle- raiser as bargainers. But as the payment would not be so high as to cause the cattle-raiser to abandon this location and as it would not vary with the size of the herd, such an agreement would not affect the allocation of resources but would merely alter the distribution of income and wealth as between the cattle-raiser and the farmer. I think it is clear that if the cattle- raiser is liable for damage caused and the pricing system works smoothly, the reduction in the value of production elsewhere will be taken into account in computing the additional cost involved in increasing the size of the herd. This cost will be weighed against the value of the additional meat production and, given perfect competition in the cattle industry, the allocation of resources in cattle-raising will be optimal. What needs to be emphasized is that the fall in the value of production elsewhere which would be taken into account in the costs of the cattle-raiser may well be less than the damage which the cattle would cause to the crops in the ordi nary course of events. This is because it is possible, as a result of market transactions, to discontinue cultivation of the land. This is desirable in all to change his crop(since this would reduce damage liability from $3 to $1)and it would be profitable for the farmer to do so if the amount received ore than $1(the redue tion in his return caused by switching crops). In fact, there would be room for a mutuall bargain in all cases in which a change of crop would reduce the amount of more than it reduces the value of the crop(excluding dam which a change in the crop cultivated would lead to an increase in the value of

THE PROBLEM OF SOCIAL COST 5 subdivision of it. Suppose, for example, that the cattle have a well-defined route, say, to a brook or to a shady area. In these circumstances, the amount of damage to the crop along the route may well be great and if so, it could be that the farmer and the cattle-raiser would find it profitable to make a bargain whereby the farmer would agree not to cultivate this strip of land. But this raises a further possibility. Suppose that there is such a well￾defined route. Suppose further that the value of the crop that would be ob￾tained by cultivating this strip of land is $10 but that the cost of cultivation is $11. In the absence of the cattle-raiser, the land would not be cultivated. However, given the presence of the cattle-raiser, it could well be that if the strip was cultivated, the whole crop would be destroyed by the cattle. In which case, the cattle-raiser would be forced to pay $10 to the farmer. It is true ,tha,t the farmer would lose $1. But the cattle-raiser would lose $10. Clear￾ly this is a situation which is not likely to last indefinitely since neither party would want this to happen. The aim of the farmer would be to induce the cattle-raiser to make a payment in return for an agreement to leave this land uncultivated. The farmer would not be able to obtain a payment greater than the cost of fencing off this piece of land nor so high as to lead the cattle￾raiser to abandon the use of the neighbouring property. What payment would in fact be made would depend on the shrewdness of the farmer and the cattle￾raiser as bargainers. But as the payment would not be so high as to cause the cattle-raiser to abandon this location and as it would not vary with the size of the herd, such an agreement would not affect the allocation of resources but would merely alter the distribution of income and wealth as between the cattle-raiser and the farmer. I think it is clear that if the cattle-raiser is liable for damage caused and the pricing system works smoothly, the reduction in the value of production elsewhere will be taken into account in computing the additional cost involved in increasing the size of the herd. This cost will be weighed against the value of the additional meat production and, given perfect competition in the cattle industry, the allocation of resources in cattle-raising will be optimal. What needs to be emphasized is that the fall in the value of production elsewhere which would be taken into account in the costs of the cattle-raiser may well be less than the damage which the cattle would cause to the crops in the ordi￾nary course of events. This is because it is possible, as a result of market transactions, to discontinue cultivation of the land. This is desirable in all to change his crop (since this would reduce damage liability from $3 to $1) and it would be profitable for the farmer to do so if the amount received was more than $1 (the reduc￾tion in his return caused by switching crops). In fact, there would be room for a mutually satisfactory bargain in all cases in which a change of crop would reduce the amount of damage by more than it reduces the value of the crop (excluding damage)-in all cases, that is, in which a change in the crop cultivated would lead to an increase in the value of production

THE JOURNAL OF LAW AND ECONOMICS cases in which the damage that the cattle would cause, and for which cattle-raiser would be willing to pay exceeds the amount which the fa would pay for use of the land. In conditions of perfect competition, the amount which the farmer would pay for the use of the land is equal to the difference between the value of the total production when the factors are employed on this land and the value of the additional product yielded in their next best use (which would be what the farmer would have to pay for the factors). If damage exceeds the amount the farmer would pay for the use of the land, the value of the additional product of the factors employed elsewhere would exceed the value of the total product in this use after damage is taken into account. It follows that it would be desirable to abandon cultivation of the land and to release the factors employed for production elsewhere. a procedure which merely provided for payment for damage to the crop caused by the cattle but which did not allow for the possibility of cultivation being discontinued would result in too small an employment of factors of produc- tion in cattle- raising and too large an employment of factors in cultivation of the crop but given the possibility of market transactions, a situation in which damage to crops exceeded the rent of the land would not endure. Whether the cattle-raiser pays the farmer to leave the land uncultivated or himself rents the land by paying the land-owner an amount slightly greater than the farmer would pay(if the farmer was himself renting the land), the final resul would be the same and would maximise the value of production. Even when the farmer is induced to plant crops which it would not be profitable to culti vate for sale on the market, this will be a purely short- term phenomenon and ay be expected to lead to an agreement under which the planting will cease The cattle-raiser will remain in that location and the marginal cost of meat production will be the same as before thus having no long-run effect on the allocation of resources IV. THE PRICING SYSTEM WITH NO LIABILITY FOR DAMAGE i now turn to the case in which, although the pricing system is assumed to work smoothly (that is, costlessly), the damaging business is not liable for any of the damage which it causes. This business does not have to make a payment to those damaged by its actions. i propose to show that the alloca- tion of resources will be the same in this case as it was when the damaging business was liable for damage caused. As I showed in the previous case that the allocation of resources was optimal, it will not be necessary to repeat this part of the argument. I return to the case of the farmer and the cattle-raiser. The farmer would suffer increased damage to his crop as the size of the herd increased. Suppose that the size of the cattle-raisers herd is 3 steers (and that this is the size of he herd that would be maintained if crop damage was not taken int account). Then the farmer would be willing to pay up to $3 if the cattle

6 THE JOURNAL OF LAW AND ECONOMICS cases in which the damage that the cattle would cause, and for which the cattlfe-raiser would be willing to pay, exceeds the amount which the farmer would pay for use of the land. In conditions of, perfect competition, the amount which the farmer would pay for the use of the land is equal to the difference between the value of the total production when the factors are employed on this land and the value of the additional product yielded in their next best use (which would be what the farmer would have to pay for the factors). If damage exceeds the amount the farmer would pay for the use of the land, the value of the additional product of the factors employed elsewhere would exceed the value of the total product in this use after damage is taken into account. It follows that it would be desirable to abandon cultivation of the land and to release the factors employed for production elsewhere. A procedure which merely provided for payment for damage to the crop caused by the cattle but which did not allow for the possibility of cultivation being discontinued would result in too small an employment of factors of produc￾tion in cattle-raising and too large an employment of factors in cultivation of the crop. But given the possibility of market transactions, a situation in which damage to crops exceeded the rent of the land would not endure. Whether the cattle-raiser pays the farmer to leave the land uncultivated or himself rents the land by paying the land-owner an amount slightly greater than the farmer would pay (if the farmer was himself renting the land), the final result would be the same and would maximise the value of production. Even when the farmer is induced to plant crops which it would not be profitable to culti￾vate for sale on the market, this will be a purely short-term phenomenon and may be expected to lead to an agreement under which the planting will cease. The cattle-raiser will remain in that location and the marginal cost of meat production will be the same as before, thus having no long-run effect on the allocation of resources. IV. THE PRICING SYSTEM WITH No LIABILITY FOR DAMAGE I now turn to the case in which, although the pricing system is assumed to work smoothly (that is, costlessly), the damaging business is not liable for any of the damage which it causes. This business does not have to make a payment to those damaged by its actions. I propose to show that the alloca￾tion of resources will be the same in this case as it was when the damaging business was liable for damage caused. As I showed in the previous case that the allocation of resources was optimal, it will not be necessary to repeat this part of the argument. I return to the case of the farmer and the cattle-raiser. The farmer would suffer increased damage to his crop as the size of the herd increased. Suppose that the size of the cattle-raiser's herd is 3 steers (and that this is the size of the herd that would be maintained if crop damage was not taken into account). Then the farmer would be willing to pay up to $3 if the cattle-

THE PROBLEM OF SOCIAL COST raiser would reduce his herd to 2 steers, up to $s if the herd were reduced to I steer and would pay up to $6 if cattle-raising was abandoned. The cattle- raiser would therefore receive $3 from the farmer if he kept 2 steers instead of 3. This $3 foregone is therefore part of the cost incurred in keeping the third steer. Whether the $3 is a payment which the cattle- raiser has to make if he dds the third steer to his herd (which it would be if the cattle- raiser was liable to the farmer for damage caused to the crop) or whether it is a sum of money which he would have received if he did not keep a third steer(which it would be if the cattle- raiser was not liable to the farmer for damage caused to the crop)does not affect the final result. In both cases $3 is part of the cost of adding a third steer, to be included along with the other costs. If the increase in the value of production in cattle-raising through increasing the size of the herd from 2 to 3 is greater than the additional costs that have to be incurred(including the $3 damage to crops), the size of the herd will be in- the cattle-raiser is liable for damage caused to the crop or no same wh creased. Otherwise it will not The size of the herd will be the same whether It may be argued that the assumed starting point-a herd of 3 steers-was bitrary. And this is true. But the farmer would not wish to pay to avo crop damage which the cattle-raiser would not be able to cause For example, the maximum annual payment which the farmer could be induced to pay ould not exceed $9, the annual cost of fencing. and the farmer would only be willing to pay this sum if it did not reduce his earnings to a level that would cause him to abandon cultivation of this particular tract of land. Furthermore the farmer would only be willing to pay this amount if he believed that, in the absence of any payment by him, the size of the herd maintained by the cattle raiser would be 4 or more steers. Let us assume that this is the case. Then the farmer would be willing to pay up to $3 if the cattle raiser would reduce his herd to 3 steers, up to $6 if the herd were reduced to 2 steers, up to $8 if one steer only were kept and up to $9 if cattle-raising were abandoned It will be noticed that the change in the starting point has not altered the amount which would accrue to the cattle-raiser if he reduced the size of his herd by any given amount. It is still true that the cattle-raiser could receive an additional $3 from the farmer if he agreed to reduce his herd from 3 steers to 2 and that the $3 represents the value of the crop that would be destroyed by adding the third steer to the herd. Although a different belief on the part of the farmer (whether justified or not)about the size of the herd that the cattle-raiser would maintain in the absence of payments from him may affect the total payment he can be induced to pay, it is not true that this different belief would have any effect on the size of the herd that the cattle-raiser will actually keep. This will be the same as it would be if the cattle-raiser had to pay for damage caused by his cattle, since a receipt foregone of a given amount is the equivalent of a payment of the same amount It might be thought that it would pay the cattle-raiser to increase his herd

THE PROBLEM OF SOCIAL COST 7 raiser would reduce his herd to 2 steers, up to $5 if the herd were reduced to 1 steer and would pay up to $6 if cattle-raising was abandoned. The cattle￾raiser would therefore receive $3 from the farmer if he kept 2 steers instead of 3. This $3 foregone is therefore part of the cost incurred in keeping the third steer. Whether the $3 is a payment which the cattle-raiser has to make if he adds the third steer to his herd (which it would be if the cattle-raiser was liable to the farmer for damage caused to the crop) or whether it is a sum of money which he would have received if he did not keep a third steer (which it would be if the cattle-raiser was not liable to the farmer for damage caused to the crop) does not affect the final result. In both cases $3 is part of the cost of adding a third steer, to be included along with the other costs. If the increase in the value of production in cattle-raising through increasing the size of the herd from 2 to 3 is greater than-the additional costs that have to be incurred (including the $3 damage to crops), the size of the herd will be in￾creased. Otherwise, it will not. The size of the herd will be the same whether the cattle-raiser is liable for damage caused to the crop or not. It may be argued that the assumed starting point-a herd of 3 steers-was arbitrary. And this is true. But the farmer would not wish to pay to avoid crop damage which the cattle-raiser would not be able to cause. For example, the maximum annual payment which the farmer could be induced to pay could not exceed $9, the annual cost of fencing. And the farmer would only be willing to pay this sum if it did not reduce his earnings to a level that would cause him to abandon cultivation of this particular tract of land. Furthermore, the farmer would only be willing to pay this amount if he believed that, in the absence of any payment by him, the size of the herd maintained by the cattle raiser would be 4 or more steers. Let us assume that this is the case. Then the farmer would be willing to pay up to $3 if the cattle raiser would reduce his herd to 3 steers, up to $6 if the herd were reduced to 2 steers, up to $8 if one steer only were kept and up to $9 if cattle-raising were abandoned. It will be noticed that the change in the starting point has not altered the amount which would accrue to the cattle-raiser if he reduced the size of his herd by any given amount. It is still true that the cattle-raiser could receive an additional $3 from the farmer if he agreed to reduce his herd from 3 steers to 2 and that the $3 represents the value of the crop that would be destroyed by adding the third steer to the herd. Although a different belief on the part of the farmer (whether justified or not) about the size of the herd that the cattle-raiser would maintain in the absence of payments from him may affect the total payment he can be induced to pay, it is not true that this different belief would have any effect on the size of the herd that the cattle-raiser will actually keep. This will be the same as it would be if the cattle-raiser had to pay for damage caused by his cattle, since a receipt foregone of a given amount is the equivalent of a payment of the same amount. It might be thought that it would pay the cattle-raiser to increase his herd

THE JOURNAL OF LAW AND ECONOMICS above the size that he would wish to maintain once a bargain had been made, in order to induce the farmer to make a larger total payment. and this ma be true. It is similar in nature to the action of the farmer (when the cattle- raiser was liable for damage) in cultivating land on which, as a result of an agreement with the cattle-raiser, planting would subsequently be abandoned (including land which would not be cultivated at all in the absence of cattle raising). But such manoeuvres are preliminaries to an agreement and do not affect the long-run equilibrium position, which is the same whether or not the attle-raiser is held responsible for the crop damage brought about by his cattle It is necessary to know whether the damaging business is liable or not for damage caused since without the establishment of this initial delimitation of rights there can be no market transactions to transfer and recombine them But the ultimate result (which maximises the value of production) is pendent of the legal position if the pricing system is assumed to work wit cost V. THE PROBLEM ILLUSTRATED ANEW The harmful effects of the activities of a business can assume a wide variety of forms. An early English case concerned a building which, by obstructing currents of air, hindered the operation of a windmill. A recent case in Florida concerned a building which cast a shadow on the cabana, swimming pool and sunbathing areas of a neighbouring hotel. The problem of straying cattle the two preceding sections, although it may have appeared to be rathe.3 and the damaging of crops which was the subject of detailed examination ne example of a problem which arises in many different guises. To clarify the nature of my argument and to demonstrate its general applicability, i propose to illustrate it anew by reference to four actual cases Let us first reconsider the case of Sturges v. Bridgman' which I used as an illustration of the general problem in my article on"The Federal Communi cations Commission. In this case a confectioner (in Wigmore Street)used two mortars and pestles in connection with his business (one had been in operation in the same position for more than 60 years and the other for more han 26 years). a doctor then came to occupy neighbouring premises (in Wimpole Street). The confectioner's machinery caused the doctor no harm until, eight years after he had first occupied the premises, he built a consulting room at the end of his garden right against the confectioner's kitchen It was hen found that the noise and vibration caused by the confectioner's machin- 5 See Gale on Easements 237-39(13th ed M. Bowles 1959) See Fontainebleu Hotel Corp. v. Forty-Five Twenty-Five, Inc ., 114 So, 2d 357(1959) 11Ch.D.852(1879)

8 THE JOURNAL OF LAW AND ECONOMICS above the size that he would wish to maintain once a bargain had been made, in order to induce the farmer to make a larger total payment. And this may be true. It is similar in nature to the action of the farmer (when the cattle￾raiser was liable for damage) in cultivating land on which, as a result of an agreement with the cattle-raiser, planti~ng would subsequently be abandoned (including land which would not be cultivated at all in the absence of cattle￾raising). But such manoeuvres are preliminaries to an agreement and do not affect the long-run equilibrium position, which is the same whether or not the cattle-raiser is held responsible for the crop damage brought about by his cattle. It is necessary to know whether the damaging business is liable or not for damage caused since without the establishment of this initial delimitation of rights there can be no market transactions to transfer and recombine them. But the ultimate result (which maximises the value of production) is inde￾pendent of the legal position if the pricing system is assumed to work without cost. V. THE PROBLEM ILLUSTRATED ANEW The harmful effects of the activities of a business can assume a wide variety of forms. An early English case concerned a building which, by obstructing currents of air, hindered the operation of a windmill.5 A recent case in Florida concerned a building which cast a shadow on the cabana, swimming pool and sunbathing areas of a neighbouring hotel.6 The problem of straying cattle and the damaging of crops which was the subject of detailed examination in the two preceding sections, although it may have appeared to be rather a special case, is in fact but one example of a problem which arises in many different guises. To clarify the nature of my argument and to demonstrate its general applicability, I propose to illustrate it anew by reference to four actual cases. Let us first reconsider the case of Sturges v. Bridgman7 which I used as an illustration of the general problem in my article on "The Federal Communi￾cations Commission." In this case, a confectioner (in Wigmore Street) used two mortars and pestles in connection with his business (one had been in operation in the same position for more than 60 years and the other for more than 26 years). A doctor then came to occupy neighbouring premises (in Wimpole Street). The confectioner's machinery caused the doctor no harm until, eight years after he had first occupied the premises, he built a consulting room at the end of his garden right against the confectioner's kitchen. It was then found that the noise and vibration caused by the confectioner's machin￾s See Gale on Easements 237-39 (13th ed. M. Bowles 1959). 6 See Fontainebleu Hotel Corp. v. Forty-Five Twenty-Five, Inc., 114 So. 2d 357 (1959). 711 Ch. D. 852 (1879)

THE PROBLEM OF SOCIAL COST ery made it difficult for the doctor to use his new consulting room. "In partic ular... the noise prevented him from examining his patients by auscultation for diseases of the chest. He also found it impossible to engage with effect in any occupation which required thought and attention "The doctor therefore brought a legal action to force the confectioner to stop using his machinery The courts had little difficulty in granting the doctor the injunction he sought. "Individual cases of hardship may occur in the strict carrying out of the principle upon which we found our judgment, but the negation of the principle would lead even more to individual hardship, and would at the same time produce a prejudicial effect upon the development of land for residential The court's decision established that the doctor had the right to prevent the confectioner from using his machinery. But, of course, it would have been possible to modify the arrangements envisaged in the legal ruling by means of bargain between the parties. The doctor would have been willing to waive his right and allow the machinery to continue in operation if the confectioner would have paid him a sum of money which was greater than the loss of in- come which he would suffer from having to move to a more costly or less con- venient location or from having to curtail his activities at this location or, as was suggested as a possibility, from having to build a separate wall which would deaden the noise and vibration. The confectioner would have been will ing to do this if the amount he would have to pay the doctor was less than the fall in income he would suffer if he had to change his mode of operation at his location, abandon his operation or move his confectionery business to some other location. The solution of the problem depends essentially on whether the continued use of the machinery adds more to the confectioner's income than it subtracts from the doctor, s. But now consider the situation if the confectioner had won the case. The confectioner would then have had the right to continue operating his noise and vibration-generating machinery without having to pay anything to the doctor. The boot would have been the other foot: the doctor would have had to pay the confectioner to induce him to stop using the machinery. If the doctors income would have fallen more through continuance of the use of this machinery than it added to the income of the confectioner, there would clearly be room for a bargain whereby the doctor paid the confectioner to stop using the machinery. That is to say, the circumstances in which it would not pay the confectioner to continue to use the machinery and to compensate the doctor for the losses that this would bring(if the doctor had the right to prevent the confectioner's using his s Auscultation is the act of listening by ear or stethoscope in order to judge by sound the condition of the body. 9 Note that what is taken into account is the change in income after allowing for altera tions in methods of production, location, character of product, etc

THE PROBLEM OF SOCIAL COST 9 ery made it difficult for the doctor to use his new consulting room. "In partic￾ular . . . the noise prevented him from examining his patients by auscultations for diseases of the chest. He also found it impossible to engage with effect in any occupation which required thought and attention." The doctor therefore brought a legal action to force the confectioner to stop using his machinery. The courts had little difficulty in granting the doctor the injunction he sought. "Individual cases of hardship may occur in the strict carrying out of the principle upon which we found our judgment, but the negation of the principle would lead even more to individual hardship, and would at the same time produce a prejudicial effect upon the development of land for residential purposes." The court's decision established that the doctor had the right to prevent the confectioner from using his machinery. But, of course, it would have been possible to modify the arrangements envisaged in the legal ruling by means of a bargain between the parties. The doctor would have been willing to waive his right and allow the machinery to continue in operation if the confectioner would have paid him a sum of money which was greater than the loss of in￾come which he would suffer from having to move to a more costly or less con￾venient location or from having to curtail his activities at this location or, as was suggested as a possibility, from having to build a separate wall which would deaden the noise and vibration. The confectioner would have been will￾ing to do this if the amount he would have to pay the doctor was less than the fall in income he would suffer if he had to change his mode of operation at this location, abandon his operation or move his confectionery business to some other location. The solution of the problem depends essentially on whether the continued use of the machinery adds more to the confectioner's income than it subtracts from the doctor's.9 But now consider the situation if the confectioner had won the case. The confectioner would then have had the right to continue operating his noise and vibration-generating machinery without having to pay anything to the doctor. The boot would have been on the other foot: the doctor would have had to pay the confectioner to induce him to stop using the machinery. If the doctor's income would have fallen more through continuance of the use of this machinery than it added to the income of the confectioner, there would clearly be room for a bargain whereby the doctor paid the confectioner to stop using the machinery. That is to say, the circumstances in which it would not pay the confectioner to continue to use the machinery and to compensate the doctor for the losses that this would bring (if the doctor had the right to prevent the confectioner's using his 8 Auscultation is the act of listening by ear or stethoscope in order to judge by sound the condition of the body. 9 Note that what is taken into account is the change in income after allowing for altera￾tions in methods of production, location, character of product, etc

点击下载完整版文档(PDF)VIP每日下载上限内不扣除下载券和下载次数;
按次数下载不扣除下载券;
24小时内重复下载只扣除一次;
顺序:VIP每日次数-->可用次数-->下载券;
共45页,可试读15页,点击继续阅读 ↓↓
相关文档

关于我们|帮助中心|下载说明|相关软件|意见反馈|联系我们

Copyright © 2008-现在 cucdc.com 高等教育资讯网 版权所有