当前位置:高等教育资讯网  >  中国高校课件下载中心  >  大学文库  >  浏览文档

《货币银行学 Economics of Money and Banking》课程教学资源(经典文献)The Market for Lemons_Quality Uncertainty and the Market Mechanism

资源类别:文库,文档格式:PDF,文档页数:14,文件大小:539.25KB,团购合买
点击下载完整版文档(PDF)

@ OXFORD JOURNALS OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS The Market for Lemons: Quality Uncertainty and the Market Mechanism Author(s): George A. Akerlof Source: The Quarterly Journal of Economics, Vol. 84, No. 3(Aug, 1970), pp. 488-500 Published by: Oxford University Press StableUrl:http://www.jstor.org/stable/1879431 Accessed: 18-11-2017 16: 26 UTC JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor. org Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms Conditions of Use, available at http://about.jstor.org/terms Oxfor d University Press is collaborating with TSTOR to digitize, preserve and d extend acc to The Quarterly Journal of Economics STOR This content downloaded from 220.248.61.69 on Sat, 18 Now 2017 16: 26: 51 UTC Allusesubjecttohttp:/aboutjstor.org/terms

The Market for "Lemons": Quality Uncertainty and the Market Mechanism Author(s): George A. Akerlof Source: The Quarterly Journal of Economics, Vol. 84, No. 3 (Aug., 1970), pp. 488-500 Published by: Oxford University Press Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1879431 Accessed: 18-11-2017 16:26 UTC JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://about.jstor.org/terms Oxford University Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Quarterly Journal of Economics This content downloaded from 220.248.61.69 on Sat, 18 Nov 2017 16:26:51 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

THE MARKET FOR LEMONS QUALITY UNCERTAINTY AND THE MARKET MECHANISM GEORGE A. AKERLOF I. Introduction. 488.-II. The model with automobiles 489.-III. Examples and applications, 492.-IV. Counteracting institutions, 499.-v. Conclusion, 500. L. INTRODUCTION This paper relates quality and uncertainty. The existence of goods of many grades poses interesting and important problems fo he theory of markets. On the one hand, the interaction of quality differences and uncertainty may explain important institutions of the labor market. On the other hand this paper presents a strug- gling attempt to give structure to the statement Business in under developed countries is difficult", in particular, a structure is given for determining the economic costs of dishonesty. Additional appl ations of the theory include comments on the structure of money markets, on the notion of "insurability, on the liquidity of dur ables, and on brand-name goods There are many markets in which buyers use some market statistic to judge the quality of prospective purchases. In this case there is incentive for sellers to market poor quality merchandise, since the returns for good quality accrue mainly to the entire grou whose statistic is affected rather than to the individual seller. A result there tends to be a reduction in the average quality of goods and also in the size of the market. It should also be perceived that in these markets social and private returns differ, and therefore, in some cases, governmental intervention may increase the welfare of all parties. Or private institutions may arise to take advantage of the potential increases in welfare which can accrue to all parties By nature, however, these institutions are nonatomistic, and there- fore concentrations of power-with ill consequences of their own can develop. 中 The author would 8. He would also like Ford Foundation for financial support. downloaded from 220.248.61 69 on Sat, 18 Nov 2017 16: 26: 51 UTC Allusesubjecttohttp://about.jstor.org/term

THE MARKET FOR "LEMONS": QUALITY UNCERTAINTY AND THE MARKET MECHANISM * GEORGE A. AKERLOF I. Introduction, 488.-II. The model with automobiles as an example, 489.- III. Examples and applications, 492.- IV. Counteracting institutions, 499. -V. Conclusion, 500. I. INTRODUCrION This paper relates quality and uncertainty. The existence of goods of many grades poses interesting and important problems for the theory of markets. On the one hand, the interaction of quality differences and uncertainty may explain important institutions of the labor market. On the other hand, this paper presents a strug- gling attempt to give structure to the statement: "Business in under- developed countries is difficult"; in particular, a structure is given for determining the economic costs of dishonesty. Additional appli- cations of the theory include comments on the structure of money markets, on the notion of "insurability," on the liquidity of dur- ables, and on brand-name goods. There are many markets in which buyers use some market statistic to judge the quality of prospective purchases. In this case there is incentive for sellers to market poor quality merchandise, since the returns for good quality accrue mainly to the entire group whose statistic is affected rather than to the individual seller. As a result there tends to be a reduction in the average quality of goods and also in the size of the market. It should also be perceived that in these markets social and private returns differ, and therefore, in some cases, governmental intervention may increase the welfare of all parties. Or private institutions may arise to take advantage of the potential increases in welfare which can accrue to all parties. By nature, however, these institutions are nonatomistic, and there- fore concentrations of power - with ill consequences of their own - can develop. *The author would especially like to thank Thomas Rothenberg for invaluable comments and inspiration. In addition he is indebted to Roy Radner, Albert Fishlow, Bernard Saffran, William D. Nordhaus, Giorgio La Malfa, Charles C. Holt, John Letiche, and the referee for help and sugges- tions. He would also like to thank the Indian Statistical Institute and the Ford Foundation for financial support. This content downloaded from 220.248.61.69 on Sat, 18 Nov 2017 16:26:51 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

MARKET FOR "LEMONS": AND MARKET MECHANISM 489 The automobile market is used as a finger exercise to illustrate and develop these thoughts. It should be emphasized that this mar- ket is chosen for its concreteness and ease in understanding rather than for its importance or realism I I. THE MODEL WITH AUTOMOBILES AS AN EXAMPLE A. The Automobiles Market The example of used cars captures the essence of the problem From time to time one hears either mention of or surprise at the rge price difference between new cars and those which have just left the showroom. The usual lunch table justification for this different explanatio pure joy of owning a"new"car. We offer a phenomenon is the on. Suppose (for the sake of clarity rather thal reality) that there are just four kinds of cars. There are new cars and used cars. There are good cars and bad cars (which in America are known as"lemons). A new car may be a good car or a lemon, nd of course the same is true of used cars The individuals in this market buy a new automobile without knowing whether the car they buy will be good or a lemon. But the do know that with probability g it is a good car and with probability (1-q)it is a lemon; by assumption, q is the proportion of good cars produced and (1-q) is the proportion of lemons After owning a specific car, however, for a length of time, the car owner can form a good idea of the quality of this machine; i.e., the owner assigns a new probability to the event that his car is a lemon. This estimate is more accurate than the original estimate etry in available information has developed sellers now have more knowledge about the quality of a car than the buyers. But good cars and bad cars must still sell at the same price-since it is impossible for a buyer to tell the difference tween a good car and a bad car. It is apparent that a used car can- not have the same valuation as a new car-if it did have the sam valuation, it would clearly be advantageous to trade a lemon at the price of new car, and buy another new car, at a higher prob- ability q of being good and a lower probability of being bad. Thus the owner of a good machine must be locked in. Not only is it true that he cannot receive the true value of his car, but he cannot even obtain the expected value of a new car. Gresham's law has made a modified reappearance. For most cars traded will be the"lemonS, "and good cars may not be traded at all. The "bad"cars tend to drive out the good (in much the downloaded from 220.248.61 69 on Sat, 18 Nov 2017 16: 26: 51 UTC Allusesubjecttohttp://about.jstor.org/term

MARKET FOR "LEMONS": AND MARKET MECHANISM 489 The automobile market is used as a finger exercise to illustrate and develop these thoughts. It should be emphasized that this mar- ket is chosen for its concreteness and ease in understanding rather than for its importance or realism. II. THE MODEL WITH AUTOMOBILES AS AN EXAMPLE A. The Automobiles Market The example of used cars captures the essence of the problem. From time to time one hears either mention of or surprise at the large price difference between new cars and those which have just left the showroom. The usual lunch table justification for this phenomenon is the pure joy of owning a "new" car. We offer a different explanation. Suppose (for the sake of clarity rather than reality) that there are just four kinds of cars. There are new cars and used cars. There are good cars and bad cars (which in America are known as "lemons"). A new car may be a good car or a lemon, and of course the same is true of used cars. The individuals in this market buy a new automobile without knowing whether the car they buy will be good or a lemon. But they do know that with probability q it is a good car and with probability (1-q) it is a lemon; by assumption, q is the proportion of good cars produced and (1 - q) is the proportion of lemons. After owning a specific car, however, for a length of time, the car owner can form a good idea of the quality of this machine; i.e., the owner assigns a new probability to the event that his car is a lemon. This estimate is more accurate than the original estimate. An asymmetry in available information has developed: for the sellers now have more knowledge about the quality of a car than the buyers. But good cars and bad cars must still sell at the same price -since it is impossible for a buyer to tell the difference be- tween a good car and a bad car. It is apparent that a used car can- not have the same valuation as a new car - if it did have the same valuation, it would clearly be advantageous to trade a lemon at the price of new car, and buy another new car, at a higher prob- ability q of being good and a lower probability of being bad. Thus the owner of a good machine must be locked in. Not only is it true that he cannot receive the true value of his car, but he cannot even obtain the expected value of a new car. Gresham's law has made a modified reappearance. For most cars traded will be the "lemons," and good cars may not be traded at all. The "bad" cars tend to drive out the good (in much the This content downloaded from 220.248.61.69 on Sat, 18 Nov 2017 16:26:51 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

QUARTERLY JOURNAL OF ECONOMICS Bame way that bad money drives out the good). But the analogy with Gresham s law is not quite complete: bad cars drive out the good because they sell at the same price as good cars; similarly, bad money drives out good because the exchange rate is even. but the bad cars sell at the same price as good cars since it is impossible for a buyer to tell the difference between a good and a bad car only the seller knows. In Gresham's law, however, presumably both buyer and seller can tell the difference between good and bad money. So the analogy is instructive, but not complete B. Asymmetrical informatiom It has been seen that the good cars may be driven out of the market by the lemons. but in a more continuous case with different grades of goods, even worse pathologies can exist. For it is quite possible to have the bad driving out the not-s0-bad driving out the medium driving out the not-so-good driving out the good in such a sequence of events that no market exists at all One can assume that the demand for used automobiles depends most strongly upon two variables-the price of the automobile p and the average quality of used cars traded a, or Qd=D(p, u).Both the supply of used cars and also the average quality u will depend upon the price, or p=u(p)and S=s(p). And in equilibrium the supply must equal the demand for the given average quality, or S(p)=D(p, u(p)). As the price falls, normally the quality will also fall. And it is quite possible that no goods will be traded at e level thal e lach an example can be derived from utility theory. Assum group one a utility function U1=M+写x where M is the consumption of goods other than automobile, 4 is the quality of the ith automobile, and n is the number of auto- mobiles Similarly, let U2=M+写3/2x4 where M, I, and n are defined as before Three comments should be made about these utility func- ions: (1)without linear utility (say with logarithmic utility )one gets needlessly mired in algebraic complication. (2)The use of downloaded from 220.248.61 69 on Sat, 18 Nov 2017 16: 26: 51 UTC Allusesubjecttohttp://about.jstor.org/term

490 QUARTERLY JOURNAL OF ECONOMICS same way that bad money drives out the good). But the analogy with Gresham's law is not quite complete: bad cars drive out the good because they sell at the same price as good cars; similarly, bad money drives out good because the exchange rate is even. But the bad cars sell at the same price as good cars since it is impossible for a buyer to tell the difference between a good and a bad car; only the seller knows. In Gresham's law, however, presumably both buyer and seller can tell the difference between good and bad money. So the analogy is instructive, but not complete. B. Asymmetrical Information It has been seen that the good cars may be driven out of the market by the lemons. But in a more continuous case with different grades of goods, even worse pathologies can exist. For it is quite possible to have the bad driving out the not-so-bad driving out the medium driving out the not-so-good driving out the good in such a sequence of events that no market exists at all. One can assume that the demand for used automobiles depends most strongly upon two variables - the price of the automobile p and the average quality of used cars traded, a, or Qd = D (p, A). Both the supply of used cars and also the average quality p will depend upon the price, or p=j (p) and S=S(p). And in equilibrium the supply must equal the demand for the given average quality, or S(p) = D (p, p (p)). As the price falls, normally the quality will also fall. And it is quite possible that no goods will be traded at any price level. Such an example can be derived from utility theory. Assume that there are just two groups of traders: groups one and two. Give group one a utility function U1=M+ iXi _.1 where M is the consumption of goods other than automobiles, x4 is the quality of the ith automobile, and n is the number of auto- mobiles. Similarly, let U2 = M+ X 3/2x4 i.i where M, xi, and n are defined as before. Three comments should be made about these utility func- tions: (1) without linear utility (say with logarithmic utility) one gets needlessly mired in algebraic complication. (2) The use of This content downloaded from 220.248.61.69 on Sat, 18 Nov 2017 16:26:51 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

MARKET FOR "LEMONS: AND MARKET MECHANISM 491 linear utility allows a focus on the effects of asymmetry of informa- tion; with a concave utility function we would have to deal jointly with the usual risk-variance effects of uncertainty and the special effects we wish to discuss here (3)U, and U2 have the odd char- acteristic that the addition of a second car, or indeed a kth car, adds the same amount of utility as the first. again realism is sacri ficed to avoid a diversion from the proper focus To continue, it is assumed (1)that both type one traders and type two traders are von Neumann- Morgenstern maximizers of expected utility; (2)that group one has N cars with uniformly distributed quality r, Osrs2, and group two has no cars; (3)that the price of“ other goods”" M is unity Denote the income (including that derived from the sale of automobiles)of all type one traders as Y1 and the income of all type two traders as Y2. The demand for used cars will be the sum of the demands by both groups. When one ignores indivisibilities, the demand for automobiles by type one traders will be /p>1 A/pP S2=0. Thus total demand D(p, u)is D(p,)=(Y2+Y1)/p D(p, Y if3u However, with price p, average quality is p/2 and therefore at no price will any trade take place at all: in spite of the fact that at any given price between 0 and 3 there are traders of type one who are willing to sell their automobiles at a price which traders of type two are willing to pay downloaded from 220.248.61 69 on Sat, 18 Nov 2017 16: 26: 51 UTC Allusesubjecttohttp://about.jstor.org/term

MARKET FOR "LEMONS": AND MARKET MECHANISM 491 linear utility allows a focus on the effects of asymmetry of informa- tion; with a concave utility function we would have to deal jointly with the usual risk-variance effects of uncertainty and the special effects we wish to discuss here. (3) U1 and U2 have the odd char- acteristic that the addition of a second car, or indeed a kth car, adds the same amount of utility as the first. Again realism is sacri- ficed to avoid a diversion from the proper focus. To continue, it is assumed (1) that both type one traders and type two traders are von Neumann-Morgenstern maximizers of expected utility; (2) that group one has N cars with uniformly distributed quality x, 0l Di=O =/p p D2 =0 3u/2 3u/2. However, with price p, average quality is p/2 and therefore at no price will any trade take place at all: in spite of the fact that at any given price between 0 and 3 there are traders of type one who are willing to sell their automobiles at a price which traders of type two are willing to pay. This content downloaded from 220.248.61.69 on Sat, 18 Nov 2017 16:26:51 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

QUARTERLY JOURNAL OF ECONOMICS C. Symmetric Information The foregoing is contrasted with the case of symmetric infor mation. Suppose that the quality of all cars is uniformly distributed srs2. Then the demand curves and supply curves can be written s S(p)=N >1 S(p)=0 P3/2 In equilibrium (3)p=1 if Y2Y2, in which case the income of type two traders is insufficient to buy all N automobiles, there is a gain in utility of Y 2/2 units) Finally, it should be mentioned that in this example, if traders of groups one and two have the same probabilistic estimates about the quality of individual automobiles-though these estimates may vary from automobile to automobile-(3),(4), and(5)will still describe equilibrium with one slight change: p will then represent the expected price of one quality unit III. ExAMPLES AND APPLICATION A. Insurance It is a well-known fact that people over 65 have great difficulty in buying medical insurance. The natural questio on arises why doesn't the price rise to match the risk? Our answer is that as the price level rises the people who in sure themselves will be those who are increasingly certain that they will need the insurance; for error in medical check-ups, doctorg' sympathy with older patients and so on make it much easier for the applicant to assess the risks involved than the insurance com- pany. The result is that the average medical condition of insurance applicants deteriorates as the price level rises-with the result downloaded from 220.248.61 69 on Sat, 18 Nov 2017 16: 26: 51 UTC Allusesubjecttohttp://about.jstor.org/term

492 QUARTERLY JOURNAL OF ECONOMICS C. Symmetric Information The foregoing is contrasted with the case of symmetric infor- mation. Suppose that the quality of all cars is uniformly distributed, O1 S(p)=O p 3/2. In equilibrium (3) p=1 if Y2 Y2, in which case the income of type two traders is insufficient to buy all N automobiles, there is a gain in utility of Y2/2 units.) Finally, it should be mentioned that in this example, if traders of groups one and two have the same probabilistic estimates about the quality of individual automobiles - though these estimates may vary from automobile to automobile - (3), (4), and (5) will still describe equilibrium with one slight change: p will then represent the expected price of one quality unit. III. EXAMPLES AND APPLICATIONS A. Insurance It is a well-known fact that people over 65 have great difficulty in buying medical insurance. The natural question arises: why doesn't the price rise to match the risk? Our answer is that as the price level rises the people who in- sure themselves will be those who are increasingly certain that they will need the insurance; for error in medical check-ups, doctors' sympathy with older patients, and so on make it much easier for the applicant to assess the risks involved than the insurance com- pany. The result is that the average medical condition of insurance applicants deteriorates as the price level rises -with the result This content downloaded from 220.248.61.69 on Sat, 18 Nov 2017 16:26:51 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

MARKET FOR "LEMONS: AND MARKET MECHANISM 493 that no insurance sales may take place at any price. This is strictly analogous to our automobiles case, where the average quality of used car supplied fell with a corresponding fall in the price level This agrees with the explanation in insurance textbooks Generally speaking policies are not available at ages materially greate than sixty-five... The term premiums are too high for any but the most pessimistic(which is to say the least healthy) insureds to find attractive. Thus ere is a severe problem of adverse selection at these ages. The statisties do not contradict this conclusion. while de- mands for health insurance rise with age, a 1956 national sample survey of 2, 809 families with 8, 898 persons shows that hospital insurance coverage drops from 63 per cent of those aged 45 to 54 to 31 per cent for those over 65. And surprisingly, this survey also finds average medical expenses for males aged 55 to 64 of $88 while males over 65 pay an average of $77. While noninsured ex- penditure rises from $66 to $80 in these age groups, insured expen- diture declines from $105 to $70. The conclusion is tempting that insurance companies are particularly wary of giving medical in- surance to older people. The principle of"adverse selection"is potentially present in all lines of insurance The following statement appears in an in- surance textbook written at the Wharton School There is potential adverse selection in the fact that healt arance policy holders may to terminate their coverage due proportion of below average risks and claims might be higher than ticipated. Adverse selection"appears (or at least is possible)whenever the ndividual or group insured has freedom to buy or not to buy to choose the mount or plan of insurance, and to persist or to discontinue as a polic Group insurance, which is the most common form of medical insurance in the United States, picks out the healthy, for generally 1. Arrow's fine article, "Uncertainty and Medical Care"(American Eco 53, 1963), does not make this point explicitly. He overnment Insurance 2. 0. D. Dickerson, Heallh Insurance (Homewood, Ill: Irwin, 1959 Durance Melone Th downloaded from 220.248.61 69 on Sat, 18 Nov 2017 16: 26: 51 UTC Allusesubjecttohttp://about.jstor.org/term

MARKET FOR "LEMONS": AND MARKET MECHANISM 493 that no insurance sales may take place at any price.' This is strictly analogous to our automobiles case, where the average quality of used cars supplied fell with a corresponding fall in the price level. This agrees with the explanation in insurance textbooks: Generally speaking policies are not available at ages materially greater than sixty-five.... The term premiums are too high for any but the most pessimistic (which is to say the least healthy) insureds to find attractive. Thus there is a severe problem of adverse selection at these ages.2 The statistics do not contradict this conclusion. While de- mands for health insurance rise with age, a 1956 national sample survey of 2,809 families with 8,898 persons shows that hospital insurance coverage drops from 63 per cent of those aged 45 to 54, to 31 per cent for those over 65. And surprisingly, this survey also finds average medical expenses for males aged 55 to 64 of $88, while males over 65 pay an average of $77.3 While noninsured ex- penditure rises from $66 to $80 in these age groups, insured expen- diture declines from $105 to $70. The conclusion is tempting that insurance companies are particularly wary of giving medical in- surance to older people. The principle of "adverse selection" is potentially present in all lines of insurance. The following statement appears in an in- surance textbook written at the Wharton School: There is potential adverse selection in the fact that healthy term in- surance policy holders may decide to terminate their coverage when they be- come older and premiums mount. This action could leave an insurer with an undue proportion of below average risks and claims might be higher than anticipated. Adverse selection "appears (or at least is possible) whenever the individual or group insured has freedom to buy or not to buy, to choose the amount or plan of insurance, and to persist or to discontinue as a policy holder." ' Group insurance, which is the most common form of medical insurance in the United States, picks out the healthy, for generally 1. Arrow's fine article, "Uncertainty and Medical Care" (American Eco- nomic Review, Vol. 53, 1963), does not make this point explicitly. He em- phasizes "moral hazard" rather than "adverse selection." In its strict sense, the presence of "moral hazard" is equally disadvantageous for both govern- mental and private programs; in its broader sense, which includes "adverse selection," "moral hazard" gives a decided advantage to government insurance programs. 2. 0. D. Dickerson, Health Insurance (Homewood, Ill.: Irwin, 1959), p. 333. 3. 0. W. Anderson (with J. J. Feldman), Family Medical Costs and In- surance (New York: McGraw-Hill, 1956). 4. H. S. Denenberg, R. D. Eilers, G. W. Hoffman, C. A. Kline, J. J. Melone, and H. W. Snider, Risk and Insurance (Englewood Cliffs, N. J.: Prentice Hall, 1964), p. 446. This content downloaded from 220.248.61.69 on Sat, 18 Nov 2017 16:26:51 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

QUARTERLY JOURNAL OF ECONOMICS adequate health is a precondition for employment. At the same time this means that medical insurance is least available to those who need it most, for the insurance companies do their own"ad verse selecti This adds one major argument in favor of medicare. On a cost benefit basis medicare may pay off for it is quite possible that every individual in the market would be willing to pay the ex pected cost of his medicare and buy insurance, yet no insurance cof afford to sell him a policy-for at any price it will attract too many"lemons. The welfare economics of medicare, in this view, is exactly analogous to the usual classroom argument for public expenditure on roads. B. The Employment of Minorities The Lemons Principle also casts light on the employment of minorities. Employers may refuse to hire members of minority groups for certain types of jobs. This decision may not reflect rationality or prejudice- but profit maximization. For race may serve as a good statistic for the applicant's social background, abilities Good quality schooling could serve as a su statistic; by grading students the schooling system can give a better indicator of quality than other more superficial character- istics. As T. w. Schultz writes. The educational establishment discovers and cultivates potential talent. The capabilities of chil- dren and mature students can never be known until found and culti- vated. 6(Italics added. An untrained worker may have valuable natural talents, but these talents must be certified by the educa- tional establishment "before a company can afford to use them. The certifying establishment, however, must be credible; the unrelia bility of slum schools decreases the economic possibilities of their students This lack may be particularly disadvantageous to members of how 五-tem again taken from an insurance textbook, shows dical insurance market is from perfect competition ccident and health insur nce, Principles and Practices, New York: The Ronald Press, 1957, pp urance is not a commodity for sale on the open market Colum- downloaded from 220.248.61 69 on Sat, 18 Nov 2017 16: 26: 51 UTC Allusesubjecttohttp://about.jstor.org/term

494 QUARTERLY JOURNAL OF ECONOMICS adequate health is a precondition for employment. At the same time this means that medical insurance is least available to those who need it most, for the insurance companies do their own "ad- verse selection." This adds one major argument in favor of medicare.5 On a cost benefit basis medicare may pay off: for it is quite possible that every individual in the market would be willing to pay the ex- pected cost of his medicare and buy insurance, yet no insurance company can afford to sell him a policy - for at any price it will attract too many "lemons." The welfare economics of medicare, in this view, is exactly analogous to the usual classroom argument for public expenditure on roads. B. The Employment of Minorities The Lemons Principle also casts light on the employment of minorities. Employers may refuse to hire members of minority groups for certain types of jobs. This decision may not reflect ir- rationality or prejudice -but profit maximization. For race may serve as a good statistic for the applicant's social background, quality of schooling, and general job capabilities. Good quality schooling could serve as a substitute for this statistic; by grading students the schooling system can give a better indicator of quality than other more superficial character- istics. As T. W. Schultz writes, "The educational establishment discovers and cultivates potential talent. The capabilities of chil- dren and mature students can never be known until found and culti- vated." 6 (Italics added.) An untrained worker may have valuable natural talents, but these talents must be certified by "the educa- tional establishment" before a company can afford to use them. The certifying establishment, however, must be credible; the unrelia- bility of slum schools decreases the economic possibilities of their students. This lack may be particularly disadvantageous to members of 5. The following quote, again taken from an insurance textbook, shows how far the medical insurance market is from perfect competition: is . .insurance companies must screen their applicants. Naturally it is true that many people will voluntarily seek adequate insurance on their own initiative. But in such lines as accident and health insurance, companies are likely to give a second look to persons who voluntarily seek insurance without being approached by an agent." (F. J. Angell, Insur- ance, Principles and Practices, New York: The Ronald Press, 1957, pp. 8-9.) This shows that insurance is not a commodity for sale on the open market. 6. T. W. Schultz, The Economic Value of Education (New York: Colum- bia University Press, 1964), p. 42. This content downloaded from 220.248.61.69 on Sat, 18 Nov 2017 16:26:51 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

MARKET FOR "LEMONS": AND MARKET MECHANISM 495 already disadvantaged minority groups. For an employer may make a rational decision not to hire any members of these groups in responsible positions-because it is difficult to distinguish those with good job qualifications from those with bad qualifications This type of decision is clearly what George Stigler had in mind when he wrote, "in a regime of ignorance Enrico Fermi would have been a gardener, von Neumann a checkout clerk at a drugstore " t As a result, however, the rewards for work in slum schools tend to accrue to the group as a whole-in raising its average quality-rather than to the individual. Only insofar as informa tion in addition to race is used is there any incentive for training An additional worry is that the Office of Economic Opportunity is going to use cost-benefit analysis to evaluate its programs. For many benefits may be external. The benefit from training minority groups may arise as much from raising the average quality of the group as from raising the quality of the individual trainee; and, likewise, the returns may be distributed over the whole group rather than to the individual C. The Costs of Dishonesty The Lemons model can be used to make some comments on the costs of dishonesty. Consider a market in which goods are sold honestly or dishonestly; quality may be represented, or it may be misrepresented. The purchaser's problem, of course, is to identify quality. The presence of people in the market who are willing to offer inferior goods tends to drive the market out of existence-as in the case of our automobile"lemons "It is this possibility that represents the major dishonest dealings tend to drive honest dealings out of the market. There may be potential buyers of good quality products and there may be po- tential sellers of such products in the appropriate price range ds to ce of people who wish to pawn bad wares as good wares tends to drive out the legitimate business. The cost of dishonesty, therefore, lies not only in the amount by which the purchaser is cheated the cost also must include the lo curr from driving legitimate business out of existence Dishonesty in business is a serious problem in underdeveloped countries. Our model gives a possible structure to this statement and delineates the nature of the " external economies involved In particular, in the model economy described, dishonesty, or the 7.G. J S formation and the labor Market, Journal of politi- downloaded from 220.248.61 69 on Sat, 18 Nov 2017 16: 26: 51 UTC Allusesubjecttohttp://about.jstor.org/term

MARKET FOR "LEMONS": AND MARKET MECHANISM 495 already disadvantaged minority groups. For an employer may make a rational decision not to hire any members of these groups in responsible positions - because it is difficult to distinguish those with good job qualifications from those with bad qualifications. This type of decision is clearly what George Stigler had in mind when he wrote, "in a regime of ignorance Enrico Fermi would have been a gardener, Von Neumann a checkout clerk at a drugstore." 7 As a result, however, the rewards for work in slum schools tend to accrue to the group as a whole -in raising its average quality -rather than to the individual. Only insofar as informa- tion in addition to race is used is there any incentive for training. An additional worry is that the Office of Economic Opportunity is going to use cost-benefit analysis to evaluate its programs. For many benefits may be external. The benefit from training minority groups may arise as much from raising the average quality of the group as from raising the quality of the individual trainee; and, likewise, the returns may be distributed over the whole group rather than to the individual. C. The Costs of Dishonesty The Lemons model can be used to make some comments on the costs of dishonesty. Consider a market in which goods are sold honestly or dishonestly; quality may be represented, or it may be misrepresented. The purchaser's problem, of course, is to identify quality. The presence of people in the market who are willing to offer inferior goods tends to drive the market out of existence - as in the case of our automobile "lemons." It is this possibility that represents the major costs of dishonesty - for dishonest dealings tend to drive honest dealings out of the market. There may be potential buyers of good quality products and there may be po- tential sellers of such products in the appropriate price range; however, the presence of people who wish to pawn bad wares as good wares tends to drive out the legitimate business. The cost of dishonesty, therefore, lies not only in the amount by which the purchaser is cheated; the cost also must include the loss incurred from driving legitimate business out of existence. Dishonesty in business is a serious problem in underdeveloped countries. Our model gives a possible structure to this statement and delineates the nature of the "external" economies involved. In particular, in the model economy described, dishonesty, or the 7. G. J. Stigler, "Information and the Labor Market," Journal of Politi- cal Economy, Vol. 70 (Oct. 1962), Supplement, p. 104. This content downloaded from 220.248.61.69 on Sat, 18 Nov 2017 16:26:51 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

QUARTERLY JOURNAL OF ECONOMICS misrepresentation of the quality of automobiles, costs 1/2 unit of utility per automobile; furthermore, it reduces the size of the used car market from N to 0. We can, consequently, directly evaluate the costs of dishonesty -at least in theory There is considerable evidence that quality variation is greater in underdeveloped than in developed areas. For instance the need for quality control of exports and State Trading Corporations can be taken as one indicator. In India, for example, under the Export Quality Control and Inspection Act of 1963, "about 85 per cent of Indian exports are covered under one or the other type of quality control. Indian housewives must carefully glean the rice of the local bazaar to sort out stones of the same color and shape which have been intentionally added to the rice. Any comparison of the heterogeneity of quality in the street market and the canned qual ities of the American supermarket suggests that quality variation is a greater problem in the east than in the West In one traditional pattern of development the merchants of the pre-industrial generation turn into the first entrepreneurs of the next. The best-documented case is Japan, but this also may have been the pattern for Britain and America. In our picture the im- portant skill of the merchant is identifying the quality of merchan dise; those who can identify used cars in our example and can guarantee the quality may profit by as much as the difference be tween type two traders buying price and type one traders'selling price. These people are the merchants. In production these skills are equally necessary -both to be able to identify the quality of inputs and to certify the quality of outputs. and this is one(added) reason why the merchants may logically become the first entrepren The problem, of course, is that entrepreneurship may be a scarce resource; no development text leaves entrepreneurship un- emphasized. Some treat it as central. Given, then, that entrepre- neurship is scarce, there are two ways in which product variations impede development. First, the pay-off to trade is great for would- be entrepreneurs, and hence they are diverted from production second, the amount of entrepreneurial time per unit output greater, the greater are the quality variations 8. The ov.10,1967,p.1 the M of te university Press, 1955 P. Kindleberger, Economic Development (New York: McGraw- Hil,1958),p.86 For example, see w. Arthur Lewis, The Theory of Economic Growth (Homewood, Ill. Irwin, 1955), p. 196. This content downloaded from 220.248.61 69 on Sat, 18 Nov 201716: 26: 51 UTC Allusesubjecttohttp://about.jstor.org/term

496 QUARTERLY JOURNAL OF ECONOMICS misrepresentation of the quality of automobiles, costs 1/2 unit of utility per automobile; furthermore, it reduces the size of the used car market from N to 0. We can, consequently, directly evaluate the costs of dishonesty - at least in theory. There is considerable evidence that quality variation is greater in underdeveloped than in developed areas. For instance, the need for quality control of exports and State Trading Corporations can be taken as one indicator. In India, for example, under the Export Quality Control and Inspection Act of 1963, "about 85 per cent of Indian exports are covered under one or the other type of quality control." 8 Indian housewives must carefully glean the rice of the local bazaar to sort out stones of the same color and shape which have been intentionally added to the rice. Any comparison of the heterogeneity of quality in the street market and the canned qual- ities of the American supermarket suggests that quality variation is a greater problem in the East than in the West. In one traditional pattern of development the merchants of the pre-industrial generation turn into the first entrepreneurs of the next. The best-documented case is Japan,9 but this also may have been the pattern for Britain and America.' In our picture the im- portant skill of the merchant is identifying the quality of merchan- dise; those who can identify used cars in our example and can guarantee the quality may profit by as much as the difference be- tween type two traders' buying price and type one traders' selling price. These people are the merchants. In production these skills are equally necessary - both to be able to identify the quality of inputs and to certify the quality of outputs. And this is one (added) reason why the merchants may logically become the first entrepren- eurs. The problem, of course, is that entrepreneurship may be a scarce resource; no development text leaves entrepreneurship un- emphasized. Some treat it as central.2 Given, then, that entrepre- neurship is scarce, there are two ways in which product variations impede development. First, the pay-off to trade is great for would- be entrepreneurs, and hence they are diverted from production; second, the amount of entrepreneurial time per unit output is greater, the greater are the quality variations. 8. The Times of India, Nov. 10, 1967, p. 1. 9. See MI. J. Levy, Jr., "Contrasting Factors in the Modernization of China and Japan," in Economic Growth: Brazil, India, Japan, ed. S. Kuznets, et. al. (Durham, N. C.: Duke University Press, 1955). 1. C. P. Kindleberger, Economic Development (New York: McGraw- Hill, 1958), p. 86. 2. For example, see W. Arthur Lewis, The Theory of Economic Growth (Homewood, Ill.: Irwin, 1955), p. 196. This content downloaded from 220.248.61.69 on Sat, 18 Nov 2017 16:26:51 UTC All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

点击下载完整版文档(PDF)VIP每日下载上限内不扣除下载券和下载次数;
按次数下载不扣除下载券;
24小时内重复下载只扣除一次;
顺序:VIP每日次数-->可用次数-->下载券;
共14页,试读已结束,阅读完整版请下载
相关文档

关于我们|帮助中心|下载说明|相关软件|意见反馈|联系我们

Copyright © 2008-现在 cucdc.com 高等教育资讯网 版权所有